Psychoanalysis and Shakespeare:
Cruising the Canon
David Begelman
Psychoanalytic
approaches to Shakespeare’s plays seem to me to represent misdirections and
diversions from a proper assessment of the canon. Psychoanalytic
interpretations of the motives of, say, Hamlet and Iago, may actually fail to
do what they purport to do: explain the behavior of a central character in a
play. On one interpretation, Hamlet procrastinates avenging his father’s death
because his unconscious Oedipal fantasies would surface uncomfortably close to
consciousness were he to murder his uncle outright; Iago’s hatefulness supposedly
camouflages his homosexual desire for Othello or Cassio or both. That a generation
of scholars could take these lucubrations seriously is the thing to be
explained, not two of the most skillfully drawn personalities in all of
literature.
Latent
or unconscious homosexuality, as this is held to motivate the villain in Othello, seems to have exhausted its
panoramic grip on American letters, not to mention the preoccupations of
academics, notably professors of literature and philosophy. Many of them in the past fastened onto it as
a protean explanatory rubric. Perhaps one reason for its diminished role is the
recent drift toward abandoning outdated ideas about the Other, including persons
who maintain diverse life styles. Accordingly, repressed homosexuality in
literature and the theater seems to have run its morbid course up to a point in
time when everyone stopped being anxious about the possibility that the alleged
condition was his or hers.
American
plays in which homosexuality is an ingredient theme, like Tennessee Williams’ Cat On A Hot Tin Roof, are often those
in which the motive is not repressed, but suppressed, affording little opportunity for the psychoanalytically
inspired to do their thing. Big Daddy Pollitt, in the powerful second act of
William’s play, forces his son Brick to face the erotic, and not especially unconscious,
desire for his dead sports pal. Brick returns the lesson in truth-telling by
informing Big Daddy he is dying from colon cancer. The father, furious that his
condition has been kept from him, exits shouting that everyone—except his
tortured son—is a liar. The “odor of mendacity” on Big Daddy’s plantation is
relieved only by revelations that for father and son have been too searing to
face prior to their explosive confrontation.
Of
course, perhaps a case might be made for psychoanalysis “explaining”
Shakespearean characters were we to harbor some unusual sense of the term
“explanation” for what psychoanalysts do with fictional characters. Freud likewise
fancied he explained real individuals like Leonardo da Vinci and Michelangelo in
his 1910 and 1914 monographs. Yet it only stands to reason that a theorist who
can boldly declare, as he did in Totem
and Taboo, that Moses was an
Egyptian, deserves more in the way of skeptical reception.
Psychohistorians,
following Freud, tend to put the cart before the horse. We cannot use
psychology to recreate history before deferring to historians as fact finders.
Psychology of whatever persuasion can only elaborate on established history. In
addition, in Totem and Taboo Freud postulated
that real life Oedipal dramas of wishing to kill the father and sexually
possess the mother are actually throwbacks to a very real past, and were inherited
from the experiences of our primordial ancestors. Such a formulation
incorporates a discredited theory of genetic transmission, Lamarckianism,
allowing for the inheritance of acquired characteristics. It rose to prominence
in Soviet Russia, where Stalin’s handpicked agronomist, Trofim Lysenko, put
forth a theory on a similar wave-length. Not all Soviet howlers were in the
purely political arena.
On
April 21, 1896, when Freud presented the first of his three “Seduction Theory”
papers to the Viennese Medical Society, Richard Von Krafft-Ebing who chaired
the meeting was moved to observe that the theory “sounds like a scientific
fairy-tale.” The comment has been spun by psychoanalysts as the voice of a
medical sensibility unprepared for a pioneer well in advance of his time. Freud
himself characterized the reaction to his paper as “an icy reception from the
asses.” When he abandoned the theory
mere months after announcing it, later retractions by psychoanalysts of their attitude
to the dismissive judgment of Krafft-Ebing and his colleagues were nowhere in
sight in the turgid prose of Freud’s insular circle.
The
Welsh scholar, Peter Swales, has demonstrated that some of the patients in
Freud’s caseload were none other than himself disguised as paying customers, so
that the honesty of the founder of psychoanalysis also comes under a cloud. For
those of you who fall asleep at lectures, but can be roused to alertness when a
National Enquirer-type tidbit is
offered for consideration, should know that Dr. and Mrs. Sigmund Freud on
vacation signed in at a European hotel and shared the same room. Except the
woman was not Marthe Freud, the doctor’s wife, but Minna Bernays, his
sister-in-law. So much for bourgeois physicians of flawless integrity. Of
course, ad hominem arguments are no
substitute for dispassionate criticism of theory, even if from time to time
they are more fun.
For
what it’s worth, my hunch is that these so-called explanations have a moral, as
well as a scientific thrust. To hold that the artistic products of the two great
Renaissance painters can be explained by positing unresolved Oedipal feelings seems
to be a backhanded way of demoting artistic achievement down to a nasty level
of shared instincts. For me, the theory degrades creative achievement by
consigning it to the ranks of mundane processes. To narrow the distance between
me and Michelangelo would appear on the moral plane to demote him or elevate
me. Were psychoanalysts to protest that all their theory seeks to do is to
scientifically explain, not demote, creative genius, my response would be:
“That may be the scientific aim of the formulation; but what is its moral aim?”
Psychoanalytic
theory and its offshoot, psychoanalytic psychotherapy, are currently in
disrepute as viable avenues of explanation and treatment. In my business, the
treatment of troubled persons, psychoanalysis is largely an anachronism. I say “largely”
here because patients do sometimes improve in this kind of psychotherapy. But
they also improve in alternative forms of therapy, with a significant
contribution of what we in the trade call “non-specific factors.”
Suggestibility is a relevant component here, although behavior change in
treatment is invariably attributed to its effect, as if the logical fallacy of post hoc ergo propter hoc were too much
of a temptation for the enchanted to avoid.
The
business of evaluating the effectiveness of psychotherapy is a tremendously
complicated task for researchers. Effectiveness has to be the statistically
significant advantage of any treatment approach over the advantage of receiving
no treatment at all. Several studies, although not all, report dismal findings
in this regard. The prestigious New York Psychoanalytic Institute many years
ago undertook a study on the effectiveness of psychoanalysis. The results were
so embarrassing to the profession, authorities at the Institute immediately
suppressed the data. Evidently, for their ranks the truth not make you free.
Ironically,
the principal impetus for contemporary disenchantment with the house that Freud
built comes from humanities scholars, many of whom who were once its staunchest
supporters. I refer here to the commentary of philosophers like Adolph Grünbaum,
Frank Cioffi, and Colin McGuinn, and others like Frederick Crews, Peter Swales,
Max Scharnberg, Malcolm Macmillan, Allan Esterson, Stanley Fish, Hans J.
Eysenck, Robyn Dawes, Frank J. Sulloway, Sebastian Timpanaro, Rosemarie Sand,
and others too numerous to mention. Their disenchantment mirrors the nearly universal
although less publicized disdain for psychoanalysis in the austere corridors of
experimental psychology. Sir Peter Medawar, a Nobel Prize winner in Medicine,
characterized Freud’s theory as a “stupendous confidence trick.” I cannot emphasize
too strongly the power of this recent commentary. It is impressive and far
reaching, and not the idle chatter of a few jaded souls.
One
more point before we take up the plays. There seems to be a contemporary bias
for “getting to the bottom” of a psychological problem, a trend that has been
an unfortunate aftermath of psychoanalytic theorizing. When overemphasized—as
it is these days—one can sense the overreach of a strictly motivational psychology.
The charm of Freud’s theory in my opinion hinges on the belief that for every
pattern of overt behavior there has to be a tacit narrative making it coherent in
some scripted or literary way. This is probably why the theory has had such an
appeal for humanities scholars. They are only too willing to popularize
formulations that create subterranean texts with a motive structure all their
own, differing from the features of overt behavior. It is as if at every step
the ordinary reasons and motives for our behavior had to be deconstructed on
pain of being regarded as superficial. The tacit literary script is seen as explaining
the manifest one.
Allow
me to refer you to one aftermath of this kind of thinking. I see a number of
patients who have diagnosable panic disorder. The condition is characterized by
unpredictable anxiety episodes and can incapacitate the patient, sometimes to
the point of being housebound. The retreat maneuver is called agoraphobia, which is not as its Greek
etymology would suggest, a fear of open spaces, but a fear of an anxiety attack
in those places in which the episode previously occurred. Favorite sites for
first occurrences are expressways, shopping centers, and restaurants.
Housebound patients have agoraphobia in spades: they can have, or imagine they
can have, an attack any place outside the home site to which they have
unfortunately retreated. There are other forms of anxiety, but panic disorder
is an unusually debilitating form of the condition. It can be treated with
medication (usually a regimen of a selective serotonin reuptake inhibiter like
Prozac or Zoloft, a tricyclic antidepressant like Imipramine, or anxiolytics
like Xanax, and a cognitive-behavioral therapeutic approach involving
desensitization strategies or flooding paradigms). Sometimes one or another of
these modalities will do the trick. Panic disorder is democratic, while it affects
more women than men, its sex-linked aspect is not as strident as it is for
eating disorders (female), stuttering (male), self-mutilation (females), or
Attention Deficit Hyperactivity Disorder (male). Its sometime victims have been
the actor Phillip Bosco, the singer Carly Simon, the great operatic tenor
Franco Corelli, and Sir Laurence Olivier.
The
hitch is that there is a significant percentage of patients who refuse
medication, not because they are enamored of wholistic health or natural rather
than synthetically manufactured compounds, but because they “want to get to the
bottom of the problem.” By this they mean they want to explore to the
underlying psychodynamics of their condition, rather than rely on synthetic palliatives
like medication. Note: medication is only a band-aid in their minds, whereas
something akin to an underlying system of repressed impulses or conflicts, the
unconscious narrative, is the real culprit. I sometimes remind them that
patients with panic disorder react catastrophically to injections of Sodium Lactate,
whereas the procedure has no effect on anxiety-free controls. In addition,
there is a high concordance rate in identical twins for the disorder, and a
familial risk. Doesn’t that suggest that the problem may lie in processes
wholly outside the arena of unconscious motives? By the way, the fact that the
root cause of panic disorder may be in the physiological realm does not
preclude versions of cognitive therapies aimed at altering thinking about the
condition. After all, changed thinking about a condition also has a physical
representation in the nervous system. What won’t work is psychobabble about
unconscious motives—for good reason. Panic disorder isn’t motivated; it just
happens to people. The generalization remains true even for those episodes of
the condition that are triggered by stress-related factors.
Hamlet’s World
I
should like to quote at length a passage from Ernest Jones’ Hamlet and Oedipus to illustrate the
kind of formulation of which I speak:
Hamlet’s attitude towards his uncle-father is far more
complex than is commonly supposed. He of course detests him, but it is the
jealous detestation of one evil-doer toward his successful fellow…for the more
vigorously he denounces his uncle the more powerfully does he stimulate to
activity his own unconscious and “repressed” impulses…His own “evil” prevents
him from completely denouncing his uncle’s, and in continuing to “repress” the
former he must strive to ignore, to condone, and if possible even to forget the
latter…In reality his uncle incorporates the deepest and most buried part of
his own personality, so that he cannot kill him without also killing himself…Only
when he has made the final sacrifice and brought himself to the door of death
is he free to fulfill his duty, to avenge his father, and to slay his other
self—his uncle (Jones, 1949, p. 100).
There
are several peculiarities in this short exposition of one influential
psychoanalyst’s approach to the play. First, I cannot fathom why Jones says
that Hamlet’s “own ‘evil’” prevents him from denouncing his uncle, or in
“repressing” instincts he has to ignore, condone, or even forget his uncle’s
evil deed. Hamlet denounces his uncle at every turn in the play, and he is
hardly given to either ignoring, condoning, or forgetting the idea his uncle
murdered his father at any point beyond the initial scene when he encounters
the ghost for the first time. Quite the reverse. But if the so-called Oedipal
conflict were the operative subtext of Hamlet’s character, would not Jones’
formulation lead to the expectation that Hamlet would indeed either condone or
forget what his father’s ghost had revealed to him on the battlements of
Elsinore Castle?
To illustrate the suspiciously comprehensive
texture of psychoanalytic theorizing, suppose I were to author a play about a
prince who learns that his uncle had murdered his father and married his mother
within a month after his father’s death. His immediate temptation is to kill
his uncle, but the more he thinks about this, the more he lapses into a
lassitude about his plans, continually forgetting about having formulated it,
and at other times coming up with reasons why his uncle’s act might have been
politically justified. What would the psychoanalysts say? Why, that I had just
written a play about a hero whose behavior can be explained by his repressed Oedipal
fantasies—exactly the same explanation that Jones fashions to explain the
behavior of Shakespeare’s Hamlet, a character who does the opposite of the hero
in my play. And here we have an excellent illustration of what psychoanalysts tend
to do with any scenario. It is always reduced to the same equation no matter
what the manifest scenario. Formulations that explain everything explain
nothing. Just what scenario might it be that would, on Sir Karl Popper’s
criterion of scientific legitimacy, count as falsifying psychoanalytic interpretation?
The
above point was driven home for me when, years ago I was invited to the home of
an analyst for a summer weekend. A sign above the front door of his cottage on
Fire Island read “Oedipus Rex.” My host was a chess player, and during a match
with him I had the occasion to remark that Dr. Reuben Fine, another
psychoanalyst, had authored a paper on the Oedipal fantasies inherent in chess.
My host scoffed at the very idea, since for him Oedipal fantasies cut across
all kinds of behavior, so it was no news it should make a similar appearance in
chess. If white plays P-K4, the player is unconsciously preoccupied with the
father figure, with the intent of murdering him; if he plays P-Q4, he is
preoccupied with the mother, possibly to sexually possess her after murdering
the father figure; if he plays N-KB3 or N-QB3, he is intent on bypassing or
repressing his unconscious preoccupation with Kings and Queens. All these moves
are popular ones in chess because they
are dictated by rules governing the opening game. That is, there are
strategic reasons for the moves in question, and these have absolutely nothing
to do with the unconscious psychology of players, unless we mean by this their
unverbalized, albeit rational decision-making based upon certain rules of the
game.
Jones
goes on to develop his thesis of Hamlet driven by the incestuous idea of
sexually possessing his mother. His explanation for Hamlet’s being able to kill
Claudius at the end of the play bears scrutiny:
There are two moments in the play when he is nearest to
murder, and it is noteworthy that in both the impulse has been dissociated from
the unbearable idea of incest. The second is of course when he actually kills
the King, when the Queen is already dead and lost to him for ever, so that his
conscience is free of an ulterior motive for the murder (Jones, 1949, p. 100).
Jones implies that the unconscious
wishes responsible for Hamlet’s delay in killing his uncle Claudius no longer activate
inaction after his mother Gertrude dies from poison. How is such an assumption derived,
even from the psychoanalytic formulation? If the Oedipal conflict is the chief
player in Hamlet’s unconscious, whence the deduction it is less instrumental because
of the real demise of the mother figure? In other words, why should Gertrude’s
death have any bearing at all on Hamlet’s weakened inhibitions to avenge his
father? Jones here fudges deductions that reconcile Hamlet’s murder of Claudius
with the hypothesized reasons for his being unable to do so—right up to the
point he actually follows through with the deed.
In
the play there was an actual attempt on Hamlet’s part to kill his uncle—thus
refuting the psychoanalytic stress on unconsciously derived delay, although
Jones fudges the point in a like-minded way. This is the scene in Gertrude’s
chamber when Hamlet stabs an intruder hiding behind an arras:
How
now, a rat? Dead for a ducat dead. Thou wretched, rash, intruding fool:
farewell: I took thee for thy better (Italics
mine—DAB)
Polonius is, at
the Danish court, an adviser who appears to be the closest to being a prime
minister. There is no “better” above him as far as social station is concerned except
royalty, like Hamlet, Claudius, and Gertrude. The implication is clear: Hamlet
thought he was killing Claudius, mistaking Polonius for him. Jones’ spin on
this, a convoluted explanation of why Hamlet’s Oedipal conflict prevented him
from killing his uncle prior to his mother’s actual demise, is as follows:
…Hamlet
did not have the king in his mind when he struck this blow…After all, he had
just left the king engrossed in prayer, and the latter could hardly have rushed
in front of him to the bedroom. The words that have given rise to the common
misunderstanding (“I know not. Is it the king?”) are surely to be read as a
response to his mother’s alarm, combined with a typically irrational “wish-fulfilment”
that his task has by a lucky accident been accomplished. “Thou wretched, rash,
intruding fool, farewell: (insert: for a moment) I took thee for the better”
comes then when he realizes the impossibility of his previous thought (or
wish). Soon after this the ghost appears, which would have been superfluous had
Hamlet seriously intended to kill the king, and Hamlet admits his recalcitrance
(Jones, 1949, p. 37).
This
will never do. The appearance of the ghost (whom Gertrude, unlike her son, does
not see) in no way underscores that he goads Hamlet on the supposition the
latter has lost completely the intention to avenge him; he comes as a reminder
to expedite the matter, since getting on with it should move ahead
expeditiously, and give no sign of “blunted purpose.” The ghost announces his
visitation is only to “whet,” not recreate, that purpose.
Furthermore, both Hamlet and
Polonius exit at the end of Act III, Scene iii, leaving the king in prayer.
There is no indication of a specific passage of time after this that would make
it implausible for Hamlet to assume it was Claudius who was hiding behind the
arras. (And who else would one assume was thus situated in Gertrude’s
bedchamber?) Hamlet arrives there after calling from within: “Mother, mother, mother!”
and the interval of time between his entrance here and his exiting from the
king’s presence is left unspecified. It could be minutes, hours, even days.
Jones has it that Hamlet is
passionate and decisive when it comes to most other matters, but dilatory when
it concerns avenging his father’s death:
Hamlet
is a man capable of very decisive action, with no compunction whatever about
killing. This could be not only impulsive, as in the killing of Polonius, but
deliberate, as in arranging for the death of Guildenstern and Rosenkrantz…He
shows no trace of hesitation when he stabs the listener behind the curtain,
leaps into the grave with Laertes or accepts his challenge to what he must know
was a duel, or when he follows his father’s spirit on to the battlements, nor
is there any lack of determination in his resolution to meet the ghost…On none
of these occasions do we find any sign of that paralysis of doubt which has so
frequently been imputed to him…the whole picture is not, as Goethe depicted,
one of a gentle soul crushed beneath a colossal task, but one of a strong man
tortured by some mysterious inhibition (Jones, 1949, pp. 37-39).
Jones’ thesis then, is that Hamlet
is a passionate and decisive person in every respect, although a hero overcome
“by some mysterious inhibition” when it comes to avenging his father. Our only
task now is to show why the psychoanalyst has not persuasively demonstrated any
mysterious inhibition to execute revenge. In fact, there is no evidence in the
text for any such thing. The idea that there is was, of course, first
formulated by Coleridge. It predates psychoanalytic speculation about Hamlet
although the latter appears to be a spin on the older formulation. In the
Olivier film of the tragedy, the action is preceded by the actor’s voice
announcing that “This is the story of a man who could not make up his mind.”
Hamlet
is banished from Denmark by the king after the killing of Polonius. He is sent
to England with Rosenkrantz and Guildenstern carrying royal letters to the English
king requesting him to assassinate Hamlet. The secrecy of the mission is in
part determined by Hamlet’s popularity with the populace, making it impolitic
for Claudius to move against Hamlet on Danish soil. After Polonius’ death,
Hamlet is obviously on the defensive, with little opportunity to exact his
revenge on the king who is himself alerted to the danger to his person that
Hamlet poses. One can, without bowdlerizing the text, imagine a palace guard
around Claudius, a natural response of royalty to perceived danger. It is not
long after his trip home that the fencing match with Laertes is arranged, and
Hamlet on that very occasion exacts his revenge. We are thus faced with
explaining the alleged “mysterious inhibition” of our hero prior to the death
of Polonius.
Without
belaboring themes of the play that have been reworked endlessly by other
Shakespearean scholars, allow me to point out that an overriding one is the
playwright’s preoccupation with appearance versus reality. That is, characters
in the play frequently question what is real or unreal. The critic Maynard Mack
in The World of Hamlet referenced
what he calls the interrogative mood of the play. Hamlet’s killing Polonius,
for example, is a crisis point in the action that puts the hero on the defensive
because he misinterprets who lurks behind the arras. Hamlet’s very first speech
in Act I, scene ii begins with a world play on the theme:
Queen: If it be,
Why seems it so particular with thee?
Hamlet: Seems madam? Nay, it is. I know not
‘seems.’
The theme is
taken up with other characters, and, indeed, is registered in the very
atmosphere of the play. Especially noteworthy is Hamlet’s reflection on the
reality of the ghost in his soliloquy in Act II, scene ii: “O, what a rogue and
peasant slave am I!” This speech is important in its registering a legitimate
doubt about the meaning of the ghost’s appearance. Hamlet detested his uncle
Claudius even before the appearance of the ghost on the Elsinore ramparts: “So excellent
a king, that was to this Hyperion to a satyr.” The ghost’s revelations that
Claudius was both a murderer and an
adulterer, resonate with Hamlet’s already established intimations: “O my
prophetic soul!” meaning that he suspected something underhanded about his
uncle, if not the actual sins the ghost enumerates.
A psychoanalyst may conjecture that
Hamlet’s doubts about the ghost is simply the temporizing effect introduced by
the unconscious Oedipal conflict, but such a slant ignores the Elizabethan spin
on matters theological, especially when it came to ghostly visitations.
Hamlet’s doubts about the ghost were the entirely legitimate ones driven by the
early modern thinking about the wiles of the Devil:
…The spirit that I have seen
May be a devil, and the devil hath
power
T’assume a pleasing shape, yea,
and perhaps
Out of my weakness and my melancholy,
As he is very potent with such spirits,
Abuses me to damn me.
Are these
reservations about the ghost the transparent rationalizations for inaction the
psychoanalysts would have us believe? Or are they the very real doubts Hamlet
should harbor, given the thinking about the Devil that was dictated by the
theology of an age?
No comments:
Post a Comment