Eric Bentley on Affective Memory
David Begelman
Affective memory. Technique, advocated by
STANISLAVSKY and much elaborated in the METHOD, of re-creating emotions on
stage by mental reference to experiences in the actor’s own life (Taylor,
1966).
In
an article published originally in the Tulane Drama Review and
subsequently anthologized, Eric Bentley criticized acting theorists like
Stanislavsky and Robert Lewis, as well as translators of Stanislavsky like
Magarshack, for their views on affective memory, a.k.a. emotional memory
(Bentley, 1962). Bentley felt a more searching examination of one of the
cornerstones of so-called “Method acting” was long overdue.
Among several of the
criticisms Bentley emphasized was that, contrary to Magarshack, the term
“affective memory” did not originate with the French psychologist Theodule
Ribot, nor did it appear first in this scientist’s Problemes de Psychologie
Affective. Neither was it in use earlier than the term “emotional memory.”
Bentley pointed out that allusions to affective memory could be found in later
writings of the psychologist as well as in his earlier tomes, and in the works
of his contemporaries. The thrust of Bentley’s article, however, was not, as he
indicated, to dwell on minor terminological matters. His focus was a more
significant one.
Bentley has contended
that because Ribot raised questions about the actual availability of any such
capacity as “affective memory,” there is a disconnect between theories about it
propounded separately by Stanislavsky and the French psychologist. Bentley
avers that Ribot, from what appeared to have been a skeptical standpoint,
broached an issue over the universality of affective memories: whether people
can harbor them spontaneously at all, not whether they can be “induced by exercises”
(Bentley, 1962, p. 129). In this connection, Bentley says that Ribot finally
concluded that some persons have affective memories, others not at all,
prompting Bentley to argue that “… when Mr. Robert Lewis speaks of Emotional
Memory as something that is ‘accomplished’ he is not talking about what Ribot
was talking about” (Bentley, 1962, p. 129). Bentley’s conclusion is a non
sequitur.
Even were we to grant
Ribot’s assumption that affective memories do not as a rule occur frequently or
spontaneously, or that his contemporaries even doubted their existence, it does
not follow that they cannot denote precisely those psychological states
Stanislavsky and Lewis insisted are developed through certain exercises.
Doesn’t the very notion of an “exercise” imply a regimen necessary to install
in order to accomplish something ordinarily harder to create without it? If so,
there is no glaring inconsistency between holding that an ability is rare or
nonexistent in many and believing it can be cultivated through a particular
approach to actor training.
Even at that, there is
some ambiguity in the language of discussion. Bentley never clarified whether
Ribot’s contemporaries deemed affective memory nonexistent in the sense of “not
ordinarily operating” or “incapable of being experienced” Understandably, the
latter meaning of the term is quite an inferential stretch from observations of
infrequent patterns solely.
Bentley goes on to fault
Robert Lewis for “inverting the truth” by implying that “…though the name may
vary, the process which both the psychologists and theatre people have been
referring to is the same” (Bentley, 1962, p.129). Surprisingly, Bentley
provides little in the way of evidence for his opinion that they are not the
same. Were this not enough, Bentley goes on to personalize the issue by taking
theatre people to task for:
"…invoking scientific terminology for the sake of its
authoritative sound:
Anything with a scientific name
must have a scientific basis. Once we seethrough this fallacy, we realize that the “exercises given to actors may not
actually do the work they are supposed to do. But this is not to say they have no
value. By way of analogy, take prayer. There may not be a God sitting Up There
listening to it, but that is not to say the person praying feels no better for it…
Likewise exercises in emotional memory" (Bentley, 1962, p. 129).
It seems presumptuous to characterize distinguished
acting theorists as motivated principally by a wish to sound “scientific.”
Cannot an honest mistake—if it were one at all—be committed without a covert
attempt at scientific grandstanding? Bentley in effect is attributing base
motives to theorists without grounds for so doing. Moreover, Bentley’s
allegation is itself muddled; he has not shown that theatre people believe
anything with a scientific name must have a scientific basis. On the contrary,
the putative error Bentley presumed to expose was merely that Ribot and acting
theorists harbor similar theories about affective memory, a far cry from the
thesis that Stanislavsky’s views have no scientific basis. (As a sidebar, what
is a “scientific basis” for a viewpoint anyhow? Is it an opinion harbored by a
community of persons calling themselves “scientists”—a definition of the phrase
that historically is not inconsistent with the sometime falsity of that opinion1—or, alternatively, a demonstrable
reality that can be referenced by anyone, albeit honorifically characterized as
“scientific” because of its epistemic surety? Or does Bentley suppose,
erroneously, that the reality of any established truth is guaranteed only
through the imprimatur of a scientist?)
Bentley’s
assertion that acting exercises, like religion, have a “comforting effect,”
although hardly achieve what they were designed to accomplish is another non
sequitur. How does he parlay the fact that Stanislavsky misconstrued Ribot
into the insight that certain exercises cannot accomplish their aim—that
Stanislavsky was, as it were, kidding himself? One might just as well contend
that Method exercises, precisely because they are unrelated to the
psychological state Ribot investigated, accomplish everything intended!
Stanislavsky, Bentley insists, misread Ribot.
According to the French psychologist, “affective memory” is of dubious
prevalence. Yet Ribot’s view itself clashed with those of many colleagues of
his time: they thought the capacity didn’t exist at all! On any accounting,
this is a telling disagreement if Bentley is intent on making invidious
comparisons between the established views of psychological science and those of
particular acting theorists. In line with this, Bentley draws upon the
“scientific” viewpoint to suggest that any system of Method exercises recruited
to train actors that is based upon affective memory must be of questionable
value, although the “science” he references hardly represents a singular point
of view.
Furthermore, we must keep in mind that Ribot’s
opinions scarcely lay claim to having probative “scientific” value in the
absence of a rigorous methodology in having investigated what seems to be a
special cognitive state. Did Ribot carefully demarcate the experimental
population in which affective memory did or did not exist, and to what degree?
What was the precise methodology of his study? Was it predicated upon a
flimsier dependent variable such as gleaning verbal reports from an undefined
population of subjects? How many subjects actually comprised Ribot’s data base?
Was the possibility of transnational differences in the incidence or prevalence
of affective memory given consideration? Ribot’s conclusion was not only
contrary to the theories of some of his scientific contemporaries, it was also
partially based on his knowledge of “a contemporary man of letters…saying that
women have them and are therefore polygamous, while men don’t have them and are
polygamous” (Bentley, 1962, p. 129): as shoddy a data base—coupled with as zany
an inference—as can be imagined. “Science,” indeed!
If, as Bentley opines, it is a mistake to invoke
scientific terminology for its own sake, what about the spirit of his own
argument intending to prove Stanislavsky wrong by invoking the viewpoint of a
spokesperson who, from all appearances, represents an outdated French
psychology?2 Actually, Bentley
ignores several other alternatives that suggest themselves, to wit: (1)
Stanislavsky and Ribot referenced the same psychological state, although Ribot
was in error about its attainability, as Method exercises show; (2) Ribot was
correct about the rarity of “affective memory,” but Stanislavsky developed a
workable system of actor training, mistakenly believing it was predicated on
the same psychological capacity referenced by Ribot; (3) Ribot was wrong about
“affective memory,” which is attainable, and Stanislavsky right, although what
the two theorists separately referenced as such are actually distinguishable
capacities, like apples and oranges; (4) Ribot and Stanislavsky were both wrong
about their distinguishable notions of “affective memory”: Ribot, because his
concept pertained to an achievable state, and one not as rare as he had
supposed; Stanislavsky, because Method exercises function more like
consolations among a network of True Believers than they do effective instrumentalities.
And so on.
Bentley may have been correct in supposing that
Method exercises can be likened to “prayers in the age of science,” but he has
provided little evidence to back up his claim. And I assume that what he meant
by “the age of science” celebrates minimally an allegiance to empirical grounds
for a belief.
REFERENCES
Bentley,
E. (1962). Who was Ribot? Or:
Did Stanislavsky know any psychology? Tulane Drama Review, 7, 127-129.
Crews,
F. (1995). The Memory Wars:
Freud’s Legacy in Dispute. New York: New York Review of Books.
Crews,
F. (1998) Unauthorized Freud:
Doubters Confront A Legend. New York: Viking Press.
Dineen,
T. (1996). Manufacturing Victims:
What the Psychology Industry Is Doing To People. Montreal, Canada: Robert
Davies Multimedia Publishing.
Esterson,
A. (1993). Seductive Mirage:
An Exploration of the Works of Sigmund Freud. Chicago,
Illinois: Open Court.
Grünbaum,
A. (1984). The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A
Philosophical Critique. Berkeley, California: University of California
Press.
Macmillan,
M. (1997). Freud Evaluated: The
Completed Arc. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Nagel,
E. (1959). Methodological Issues in
Psychoanalytic Theory. In Psychoanalysis, Scientific Method and Philosophy:
A Symposium, edited by Sidney Hook, 38-56. New York: New York University
Press.
Scharnberg,
M. (1993). The Non-Authentic
Nature of Freud’s Observations (2 Volumes). Uppsala, Sweden.
Sulloway,
F. (1992). Freud, Biologist of
the Mind: Beyond the Psychoanalytic Legend. Cambridge, Massachusetts:
Little, Brown & Company.
Taylor,
J. R. (1966). The Penguin
Dictionary of the Theatre. Middlesex, England: Penguin Books Ltd.
Zilbergeld,
B. (1983). The Shrinking of
America: Myths of Psychological Change. Boston, Massachusetts: Little,
Brown & Company.
1 It was, I
believe, Sir Karl Popper, who held that the notion of the falsity of a theory
is what gives scientific theorizing not only its punch, but its virtual
significance.
2 No reflection on the French, since
outdating itself may be among the most dependable aspects of “scientific
psychology,” American variants included. If the reader is skeptical, let him or
her compare the discipline’s inconsistent pronouncements on such matters as varied
as child rearing practices, somatotyping, phrenology, intelligence quotients,
brain function, language acquisition, homosexuality, child abuse, repressed
memories, ritual abuse, and—if only to pique the complacency of a certain
professional constituency—the credibility of psychoanalytic theory (Nagel,
1959; Zilbergeld, 1983; Grünbaum, 1984; Macmillan, 1991; Sulloway, 1992;
Esterson, 1993; Scharnberg, 1993; Crews, 1995, 1998; Dineen, 1998).
No comments:
Post a Comment