Reincarnation: An
Incoherent Doctrine?
David Begelman
The
term “reincarnation” often summons up images of exotic mind-sets and religions
suffused with alien notions. Not always. Ever since the turbulent decades of
the sixties, many Americans have looked to an Eastern heritage they find
beneficial, consciousness-raising. The doctrine of reincarnation, like other
imports, now attracts a population far removed from being chanters with shaved
heads and saffron robes. And the list of embracers of the doctrine in yesteryear is
endless: Benjamin Franklin, Napoleon, Tolstoy, Henry Ford, General George S.
Patton, and numerous others. Even Hollywood celebrities have cottoned on to the
doctrine. Sylvester Stallone, Tom Cruise and John Travolta are enthusiasts, as
was the deceased Peter Sellars. Shirley MacLaine has authored best sellers
touting the doctrine and reproaching those Doubting Thomases amongst us who
pooh-pooh it as the intellectual rubbish of the gullible. At one point, she was
convinced that in a past life she was a jester who was beheaded by King Louis
XV for impertinent remarks.
As
it turns out, King Louis of France was fonder of debauchery than he was of
cruelty. He was even prepared to forgive a would-be assassin, Robert François
Damiens, for stabbing him between the ribs with a knife. There is no historical
evidence for the potentate beheading anyone—a minor detail lost in the shuffle
of enthusiasm for a doctrine that seemingly provides relief from a purely
materialistic ethos or philosophies in which matters mental or spiritual are
irretrievably wedded to as prosaic a medium as brain tissue.
Despite
the attraction reincarnation has for some, the very notion of having lived a
previous life is a derivative one. The possibility we existed before is but one
strand in a much wider mosaic called the problem of personal identity.
Philosophers from David Hume (1969) to Robert Nozick (1981) grappled with the
issue and came away chastened by its complexities. Voltaire observed that it is
no more awesome to be born twice than it is to be born once. If the self can
have multiple identities, forms, or representations, as in reincarnation, what
makes us the singular persons we are at the outset, even before a point of
identity exchange, or before the idea of a self passing from one individual to
another taxes our imagination?
A
number of published works about reincarnation in recent decades have stirred up
fresh controversy over the doctrine. Their point of departure has been the
ground-breaking studies of Dr. Ian Stevenson, of the University of Virginia
(Stevenson, 1975, 1977, 1980, 1983). This investigator believed a good case for
the doctrine can be made based upon alleged memories of thousands of children
whose statements concerning previous lives were purportedly independently
verified. The philosopher Paul Edwards in his tome, “Reincarnation: A Critical
Examination,” (2002) has disputed Stevenson’s claims on the basis of what he
considered to be the shoddy empirical support the latter mustered for the
doctrine. Others, more sympathetic to Stevenson’s approach, found Edwards’
analysis a less than searching—if somewhat intemperate—critique that foundered
on the very empiricist principles the philosopher purported to honor (Almeder,
1997; Matlock, 1997). In their opinion, Stevenson’s research is more
empirically grounded than Edwards grants.
The
controversy swirling around the doctrine is more often than not put forth as a
disagreement over the empirical support for the doctrine. In this respect,
constituencies on opposing sides of the issue would appear to run different
epistemic risks. Parapsychologists conceivably falter on the sometime
deficiency of the evidence marshaled for the doctrine, while the case for
skepticism would be weakened by instances in which the evidence is stronger
than the doubters suppose. Should the confirmation of either stance await arbitration
by data that clinch the issue, both may be likened to empirical works in
progress. There is, however, another possibility: mischaracterizing the real
nature of the problem.
In
Alexandre Dumas’s novel, “The Corsican Brothers” two brothers, Lucien and Louis
deFranchi, were originally Siamese twins separated at birth. One of the twins
informs a guest, "…however greatly we are separated, we have one and the
same body, as we had at our birth. When anything happens to one of us, be it
physical or mental, it at once affects the other." Of course, the Dumas
novel involved anachronisms. While history records the anomaly of conjoined
twins occurring as early as 1100 C. E., the first successful surgical
separation documented was in 1953, over a century after the novel was authored
in 1845. Similarly, there is probably no documented case of separated conjoint
twins who experienced each other’s feelings, memories, or presentiments after being surgically separated. (It might
be up for philosophical grabs whether sensations in a common liver compromised
by cirrhosis before surgery meant
that each twin was feeling the same pain,
much less whether they felt each other’s pain.)
The
fictional case of the deFranchi twins is intriguing from yet another
standpoint. We might describe it as a paranormal case of two people sharing
each other’s feelings, memories and thoughts. Indeed, one might argue that
there is no known naturalistic explanation of the deFranchi phenomenon—were it
true. That it is a fictional case invented by a French novelist is consistent
with the skeptical outlook holding that instances reportedly resembling it in
any way should be relegated to the dustbin of imaginary psi-capabilities like
telepathy, clairvoyance, or E.S.P. As I understand it, the skeptical position
about even these latter abilities is that empirical evidence for them has been
paltry, due to myriad factors. One has been the failure to reliably replicate
findings when such abilities are examined under controlled conditions in
numerous case studies and experiments. Another is the all too frequent record
of fraud perpetrated on observers. For a defense of parapsychology, see Utts
(1991) and Braude (2002).
What
if something like a deFranchi phenomenon were investigated, and found to be
authentic? That is, under a rigorous a set of experimental conditions some of
the feelings, thoughts, and even sensations of one twin matched, echoed, or
were a precise duplicate of those of a separated twin examined in another
geographical area. What would the conclusion be?
The
surprise is not what skeptics and parapsychologists would say, but, ironically,
what they wouldn’t say. They wouldn’t
conclude the twins are each other. Why
not? The question should be posed because ordinarily certain facts constitute a
possible case for reincarnation when one person is dead and another living, but
apparently not when two persons are contemporaries. In the latter case, the
same data become presumptive evidence for a paranormal ability like ESP or
telepathy. Accordingly, there is a disconnect between dead/living persons
confirming reincarnation and living/living persons only supporting a psi
ability like telepathy. Do the differing implications of both categories of
cases incur a charge of philosophical double-standards? If the claim that I was
someone else in a previous life is an intelligible one, it should likewise make
sense to say I am someone else who is my contemporary for similar reasons.
Conversely, if it makes no sense to say I am another living person on the basis
of certain phenomena, it hardly makes sense to say that I was a deceased one
for analogous reasons. Thereby, said the kangaroo sitting on the edge of a
precipice, hangs a tale.
A
similar, albeit different kind of challenge to our theories about individuation
is provided in the case of Krista and Tatiana Hogan, a pair of twins who are a
case of craniopagus, or being joined at the head. Their neurosurgeon, Dr.
Douglas Cochrane of the British Columbia’s Children’s Hospital, has determined
that the girls share a common thalamus, or “thalamic bridge.” The condition has
been described by other experts in the field as “unprecedented,” “ridiculously
compelling,” “mind-blowing,” and a “new life form.” The twins share each
other’s sensations. When one of the four year olds uses a pacifier, the other
twin is soothed; when one twin is pricked with a pin, the other feels the pain.
Neurologists marvel at the anomaly, yet none among their ranks has ventured the
conjecture that the twins may be each other, although they are not above
considering that they may be sharing one mind.
To
summarize: if and when we experience another living person’s thoughts,
feelings, perceptions or sensations, the parapsychologist opts for designating
them cases of ESP or telepathy, not incarnation. In other words, when I
experience something you are likewise feeling, the occult wisdom is that I am
sensing or receiving something from you, not that I am you. The logic is a stunning piece of intellectual legerdemain
contrived to avoid the dizzying prospect of having to become saddled with
sharing identities with extant others. Thus, a “memory” of a past life
inevitably confirms reincarnation, yet similar intimations in relation to
living others (if and when they occur) only suggest the operation of paranormal
broadcasting and receiving systems.
The
problem gets more complicated. First, in reincarnation what distinguishes
a “memory” of myself in a former life
from a merely batch of factual information about a deceased person recovered in
an admittedly mysterious way? What gives the information the property of
personal ownership, entitling me to call it a “memory” of mine? In other words,
one approach to the paranormal phenomenon to be explicated may only be why
someone comes to possess information about a deceased Egyptian pharaoh, a far
cry from his being that personage.
Second,
we have referred to hypothetical cases in which two contemporaries are
discovered to share feelings and sensations, and have posed the question, “Why
not a case of contemporary incarnations (CI), rather than homespun ESP or other
forms of psi phenomena representing paranormal messages between senders and
receivers?” If CI were true, it would be this on the basis of data likewise
confirming reincarnation (RI) when one of the individuals was deceased. Going
on, it is also necessary to distinguish between a paranormal doctrine and the
evidence relied on to confirm it. Any theory can be distinguished from its
evidential basis. Relativity Theory was true before the data gleaned during a
solar eclipse confirmed it. Accordingly, are we entitled to say that CI might be true without the necessary data
to confirm this?
Let’s
cut to the chase. Could I be you without being able prove this surmise? Could
we all be each other? Or are we from the outset playing havoc with the
deployment of pronouns like I and You?
The comedian Jackie Mason used the paradox to comic advantage in one of his
routines. He relates an anecdote of consulting with a psychiatrist who informed
him that he had to find his “true self.” The fee for the visit was $50. Jackie
remonstrated, “What if you were my
true self and you owe me $50. Let’s
call it even.”
ESP
and telepathy, it turns out, are more than unusual talents; they are also each
a deus ex machina of doctrinal spin.
They relieve us of the necessity of distributing our identities in the here and
now, relegating the phenomena in question to categories of receiving “messages”
from others who are our contemporaries. Thus, the uncomfortable prospect of sharing
identities with the living is preempted, because when phenomena appear to be—or
at least qualify for—cases of contemporaneous incarnations, we’ll chalk them up
to ESP or some other familiar psi ability between senders and receivers!
When
it comes to selfhood, curious and contradictory adjustments of doctrine betray
the proprietary feelings we harbor about having to piece ourselves out.
Identity exchange in reincarnation, even across hundreds or thousands of years,
may be mysterious; it nonetheless seems to be a safe bet compared to the
troubling notion of a current double self. After all, in RI one of the entities
is, to be sure, quite dead. The same economy of doctrine is captured in
connection with that controversial psychiatric anomaly, multiple personality.
We prefer to imagine the disorder to be a case of one “self” with several
facets or aspects, not several “others” or “persons” earmarked for being housed
simultaneously in one body. We feel Eve or Sybil has several faces or “alters”
because she is at bottom conflicted or ambivalent, not because she has actually
subdivided in the manner of an overripe paramecium. As if to drum home the
point, a subcommittee of the American Psychiatric Association has elected to
rename the disorder “Dissociative Identity Disorder,” lest the misinformed read
too much into the older diagnostic designation. Of course, the same committee
provides no reasons why the misinterpretation implicitly suggested by the
notion of “Multiple Personality Disorder” is the wrong one. If the disorder cannot be said to qualify for the mantle
of “multiple contemporaneous incarnations” or CI, what currently documented
data-base would?
So
reincarnationists want to have their cake and eat it too. Under their doctrine,
souls—or at least many of them—never perish since they are always passed on to
new bodies that house them; and they are never split or fragmented in the
present because when they seem to be, we’ll chalk up a case of ESP, telepathy,
or Dissociative Identity Disorder. The double standard, needless to say, is not
without risk, for consider how it all may backfire on an even paranormal
playing field. (The reader should assume that the tone of the following remarks
is ironic.)
Suppose
the dead pharaoh whose “memories” I have was not me in a past life, but only a
sender to me of a telepathic thing beamed into the future, whereas my true
incarnation is not deceased, but a living person with whom I share some
experiences. What a cosmic pickle! I have forfeited the immortality I had banked
on in being reincarnated, and have to
settle for the demeaning plight of being split and redistributed in the here
and now by sharing my identity with a contemporary other.
Reincarnation
as a doctrine comes in many forms. As conceived in Eastern religions, it has
another subtext, sometimes called “Karma.” Here, multiple incarnations are not
without an ultimate raison d’etre.
Identities supposedly move toward higher or lower levels of existence or
enlightenment, until the process ends. (Even a thinker as inveterately downbeat
as Nietzsche viewed the notion of “eternal recurrence” as attractive.) Each
sequentially reincarnated soul represents a way of resolving the “drawbacks” or
“incompleteness” of the previous one. Some sort of unraveling through ascent or
descent on a spiritual journey is implied in certain forms of the doctrine. A
past life accordingly teaches a moral lesson about the spiritual game plan for
this one. But what?
I
learn through a guru that I was a sheep in a previous incarnation. What does this
tell me about the game-plan for this one? Am I to be less sheepish, more
assertive, bold, or enterprising in this life? Am I to be more humble, or cowed
like a lamb? Should I be another kind of “shepherd,” and become a spiritual
leader, general, corporation head? Should I become a real shepherd tending
flocks? Of what, cows, sheep, ponies, parishioners? Should I campaign against
Australians on account of their inordinate mutton consumption? There are
countless “directions” suggested by a past incarnation, but precious little in
the way of rules for interpreting its significance for the present life’s game
plan. Gurus may wax eloquent about lessons to be extracted from the character
of a past life; but they are notoriously short on understanding the complexities
involved in delivering them. But then again, humility was never a strong card
among the spiritually elect.
Reincarnation
as a doctrine can play yet another role in our lives: it permits us to pass the
buck. Shirley MacLaine (1983) writes about her romantic liaison with a married
man—a harried, insensitive type who fails to meet her emotional needs. Unable
(or unwilling) to terminate her relationship with him, the actress asks him to
consider the possibility they were lovers in a previous life. The surmise is
revealing. Rather than confront the drawbacks of the relationship squarely, the
actress preferred to fetch around for a metaphysical alibi to rationalize her
inaction. After all, if one harbored underlying misgivings about a liaison, but
for some reason was unable to sever it, wouldn’t reincarnation confer upon it a
certain stamp of inevitability? It’s difficult to envision how being lovers a
second time around dramatizes the need to end the match at the earliest
opportunity! If the spiritual whatchamacallit has the thing recycled, who are
we to resist the divine repatterning?
Reincarnation is certainly intriguing from
the standpoint of what belief in it teaches us about ourselves. Even our
self-deceits are endearing, because no doctrine, religious or otherwise, is as
beautiful as we are—nor as slippery.
References.
Almeder, R. 1997.
A critique of arguments offered against reincarnation. Journal of Scientific Exploration, Volume 2, No. 4, 499-526.
Braude, S. E.
2002. ESP and Psychokinesis: A Philosophical Examination, Revised Edition.
Parkland, Florida: Brown Walker Press.
Edwards, P. 2002.
Reincarnation: A Critical Examination. Amherst, New York: Prometheus Press.
Hume, D. 1969. A Treatise of Human Nature.
England: Penguin.
MacLaine, S. 1983.
Out on A Limb. New York: Bantam
Books.
Matlock, J. G.
1997. Review of Reincarnation: A Critical
Examination by Paul Edwards. Journal of Scientific Exploration, Volume 2,
No. 4, 570-573.
Nozick, R. 1981.
Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge,
Massachusetts: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Stevenson, I.
1975. Cases of the Reincarnation Type (Volume I). Charlottesville, Va.:
University Press of Virginia.
__________. 1977.
Cases of the Reincarnation Type (Volume II). Charlottesville, Va.: University
Press of Virginia.
__________. 1980.
Cases of the Reincarnation Type (Volume III). Charlottesville, Va.: University
Press of Virginia.
__________. 1983.
Cases of the Reincarnation Type (Volume IV). Charlottesville, Va.: University
Press of Virginia.
Utts, J. (1991).
Replication and Meta-Analysis in Parapsychology, Statistical Science, Vol. 6, No. 4, 363-403.
No comments:
Post a Comment