Freud as Degenerate: Psychoanalysis, the Seduction Papers, and Racial
Theory
D. A. Begelman, Ph.D.
A
neglected but important aspect of Freud’s formulations during what Young-Bruel
(1994) has termed the originary decade of psychoanalytic theory, from 1890 to
1900, has already been dealt with to some extent by others (Stewart, 1976;
Sulloway, 1992; Gilman, 1993a, 1993b). Essentially, it is a subtext of
theorizing involving the notion of degeneration,
a widespread preoccupation within Victorian medical circles. As then
understood, degeneration conflated ideas of psychiatric disorder, ethnicity,
and the hereditary transmission of traits. It figured negatively (1) in Freud’s Seduction Theory (ST), which,
while a predominantly environmentalist account of the psychoneuroses, was
tacitly wedded to his wish to “dislodge heredity” as a formative factor. He
says as much at key junctures in his three seduction papers of 1896: Heredity and the Etiology of the Neuroses (Freud,
1896a), Further Remarks on the
Neuro-Psychoses of Defence (Freud, 1896b), and The Aetiology of Hysteria (Freud, 1896c), as well as in his
correspondence with Wilhelm Fliess (Masson, 1985, pp. 264-266).
On the first occasion of Freud’s public repudiation
of the ST, in his Three Essays On the
Theory of Sexuality (Freud, 1905), we find him still dismissing the role of
heredity in explaining sexual inversion. Freud first alluded to the ST in
October of 1895, in one of his numerous letters to Wilhelm Fliess. What might
be characterized as the “official” story in the minds of many of Freud’s
followers and biographers has been summarized as follows:
During the 1890s, when Freud was
energetically searching for an explanation of the causes of the neuroses, many
of his patients reported that they had been sexually abused in early childhood.
Freud became convinced that in eliciting the accounts of infantile assaults he
had indeed found what he was seeking, and announced the fact in a number of
papers. However, he eventually came to realize that he had been deceived, and
that in most cases the assaults had not actually occurred. This led to the
revolutionary discovery that the events in question had been phantasied by his
patients, and from this he developed the theory of infantile phantasies which
became one of the cornerstones of classical psychoanalytic theory (Esterson,
1993, p. 11).
Of the three seduction papers, The Aetiology of Hysteria focuses
primarily on Freud’s arguments for the reality of infantile seductions. It has
been given the most critical attention in recent years, in part due to Jeffrey
Masson’s book The Assault on Truth (Masson,
1984). Masson argued that Freud’s abandonment of the ST, based as it was on the
view that his patients’ reports of early sexual abuse were fantasies rather
than realities, was a mistake. According to Masson, the abuse was real, not
imagined. Masson also contends that the switch from reality to fantasy sprang
from less than honorable motives on Freud’s part. Among these was the need to
exonerate his mentor, Wilhelm Fliess, from a charge of medical incompetence in
the Emma Eckstein case.
Nineteen months (2)
after the delivery of The Aetiology of
Hysteria to the Viennese Medical Society and in a letter to Fliess dated
September 21, 1897, Freud indicated he no longer believed in the ST. The
admission is startling for several reasons. First, it drenches in irony Freud’s
bitterness over what he felt was a hostile reaction to the paper by the medical
group to which it was presented. Since Freud himself abandoned the ST months
after delivering his paper, what was the justification for his indignation at
colleagues who felt the same way a short time earlier?
Second, the actual reasons Freud adduced for
abandoning the ST are paradoxical. Among several he enumerated in the letter to
Fliess were: (1) he had been unable to bring even one analysis to a successful
conclusion, noting an “absence of complete successes” upon which he depended;
(2) the fact that his “partial successes” might admit of alternative
explanations; (3) that the ST was predicated upon an epidemiological paradox: a
prevalence of sexual abuse implausibly high to accept as a true sociological
picture, and that (4) he was unable to distinguish truth from fantasy. In the September,
1897 letter to Fliess, Freud stated that because of these four considerations,
he was moved to give up his “neurotica” (i.e., the ST), and no longer knew
where he stood theoretically. These explanations for his reversal bear further
critical scrutiny.
(1) Incomplete
Successes. This reason for abandonment of the ST seems odd in the light of
Freud’s obvious enthusiasm about therapeutic successes when he delivered his
third seduction paper. Despite this, his expression of disappointment is
difficult to assess in advance of understanding what he meant by “a successful
conclusion.” As in the case history of Frau P., clinical outcomes routinely
counted as “successes” are frequently admixtures of favorable and unfavorable
results. Given this, how did the actual course of improvement in such a case
bear on any definition of “cure” or “successful conclusion” motivating Freud to
rework his etiological formulation in 1897? In other words, if Frau P’s
checkered therapeutic history paralleled those of other patients in Freud’s
caseload, how did the character of such clinical courses fuel doubts he began
to harbor about the ST?
Frau P.’s analysis was reported by Freud to culminate in the remission
of psychotic symptoms, maintained up to the authorship of his second seduction
paper. In the paper, Freud indicated that an exacerbation of symptomatology all
but nullified the gains of treatment, at which point Frau P. was given
institutional care. Despite the clinical regression, she rallied and returned
home. Improvement lasted another twelve to fifteen years, and she functioned
well enough to carry on household responsibilities. The only reported sign of
morbidity was her ostensible avoidance of contact with family members. Her
symptoms returned once again later on in her life, whereupon she was
rehospitalized, only to die of pneumonia in an asylum (Freud, 1896b, pp.
175-183). Since the onset of Frau P.’s problem coincided with a post-partum
period, it possible that the psychosis was precipitated by this crucial life
phase.
Rosy conceptions of “cure” often enjoy a
connotation that fail to match the realities of clinical practice—whatever the
condition. Clinicians who pin their hopes on making perfectionist criteria
probative of their etiological formulations will frequently have to confront
standards of “cure” unworkably stringent as requirements of serviceable
theories. Accordingly, a question arises over whether Freud’s 1897 standard of
“success” involved an overly idealistic one. Did “cure” for him mean complete
remission of symptoms with no possibility of relapse? Some salient symptoms?
Most symptoms? If the first of these possibilities, it is doubtful whether any post-1897 adjustments of theoretical
perspective would meet the demands of such idealistic criteria of treatment
“success.” The idea of fantasies of seduction as pathogenic would also appear
to have been no more consistent with therapeutic results than the ST discarded
for this reason.
The issue of therapeutic success is important
in another respect. It bears on a larger and more contentious issue of the
relationship between Freud’s theories and the efficacy of psychoanalytic
treatment procedures (3_. Whatever his later
convictions, there is ample indication that in 1896 Freud relied heavily on
therapeutic outcome as probative of theory confirmation. In The Aetiology of Hysteria, for example,
he avers that in eighteen cases, his theory was confirmed by “therapeutic
success” in every single case (Freud, 1896c, p. 199). At least his
self-professed reasons for giving up his “neurotica” imply the same standard.
In Further Remarks on the Neuro-Psychoses
of Defence, Freud avers that when repressions of memories of early
seduction scenes are lifted, patients’ problems are “resolved” (Freud, 1896b,
p. 174).
Elsewhere, Freud laments the therapeutic
upshot of analyses lagging behind if one has not penetrated earliest sexual
trauma, implying that desired results are contingent upon unearthing such
memories. Here, his conviction about the connection between correct interpretation
and treatment cure is obvious, although one may raise a question about the
logical status of the linkage. If Freud held to conceptually independent
criteria of “cure” and “correct analysis,” his 1897 contention that the
majority of his unresolved cases represented “incomplete analyses” was an
empirical one. On the other hand, it is possible Freud may have fudged the
point for the purposes of making forays into fresh theoretical territory. This
would have been the case had he married the correctness of a theoretical
formulation to beneficial results obtained in the consulting room. Whatever the
case, there can be little doubt that in 1896 Freud was depending in large
measure on therapeutic success as a yardstick of theoretical legitimacy.
In
Heredity and the Aetiology of the Neuroses, Freud declared that even his
approach to stock or concurrent causes, stressors which may
enter into the causation of the psychoneuroses, but are not “indispensable for
the production of the latter” bore fruit (Freud, 1896a, p. 147). His proviso
here, however, was that treatment focusing exclusively upon such factors cannot
be shielded from the possibility of relapse. The implication is clear:
treatment aimed at causes specific to these disorders, memories of sexual trauma,
when “complete,” is immunized from relapse. The need to trace associations back
to infantile sources in this phase of Freud’s theorizing was based upon his
assumption that only such a strategy would guarantee permanent cure of the
psychoneuroses. Accordingly, in the absence of the presumed connection between
his therapeutic strategy and “cure,” the approach would be a fruitless one.
That is, if in 1896 any technique founded upon alternative etiological
assumptions was able to eradicate permanently all signs of neurotic disorder,
the need to probe pre-adolescent memories of sexual trauma would be redundant.
In such an event, the very basis for suspecting a connection between disorder
and early sexual abuse would be weakened or nullified. Lasting symptom removal
would then not be the upshot of a “deep analysis” exclusively. Consequently,
the latter could not then monopolize the preferred approach or underscore a
proper view of etiology.
In fact, Freud thought along roughly similar
lines. One of his self-professed reasons for revising his outlook in 1897 was
that the clinical course of his treatment cases suggested that the actual
pathogen had to be driven back into the head. Actual sexual trauma, while
capable of intensifying a clinical disorder—Freud subsequently did not come to
deny either its existence or its role in exacerbating symptoms—no longer
qualified as the true cause of the psychoneuroses. It was superseded by the
unconscious process of organismic and essential, not merely accidentally
heightened or externally derived, sexuality. It was Freud’s 1896 conviction
that durable clinical results were exclusively the upshot of methods wedded to
proper interpretations. During that time, he held fast to this belief, as well
as its corollary: the failure to eradicate symptoms was a presumptive
indication that an analysis had not been “complete,” had not dug deeply enough.
(2) Alternative
Explanations. This reason for abandoning the ST remains a mystery, inasmuch
as the possibility of alternative explanation is a theoretical risk of any
formulation in the sciences, including those hypothetically associated with
producing “complete” cures, however these are defined. It was not the fact that
Freud’s cures were “incomplete” that increased the likelihood of the possibility
of alternative explanations to the ST, since the same possibility existed had
Freud produced the type of cure he sought in every case.
Vacillating emphases on the “completeness” or
“incompleteness” of his cures in the originary canon seems to have kept pace
with Freud’s shifting enthusiasms for particular theories. When promoting the
ST in 1896, he proclaimed “complete cure,” using methods that owed allegiance
to this theory, whereas in 1897 and thereafter he complained that the curative
picture was grimmer than he had earlier indicated. In Heredity and the Aetiology of the Neuroses, and contrary to his
1897 pronouncements, Freud asserts that the symptoms of hysteria4 can only be understood if they are
traced back to traumatic sexual experiences. How can hysteria only be understood as the delayed effect
of sexual trauma when alternatives to such a formulation exist—and indeed
existed by Freud’s own 1897 admission? Was Freud unaware of the possibility of
alternative explanation in 1896, or did his enthusiasm for the ST at that time
drown out the promptings of theoretical open-mindedness?
One of Freud’s specific examples of an
alternative to the ST during the originary period was masturbation. Long held
to be a chief cause of neurotic disturbance by Victorian medicine
generally—atavisms of its dire consequences on development still resound in
corridors of sensibility resistant to disengaging religious dogma from
scientific knowledge—it was dismissed by Freud in Further remarks On the Neuro-Psychoses of Defence as the true basis
for the psychoneuroses. Although found “side by side with hysteria, this is due
to the circumstance that masturbation itself is a much more frequent
consequence of abuse or seduction than is supposed” (Freud, 1896b, p.165). The argument
begs the question, since its conclusion is arbitrarily selective about
causality when the factors under consideration covary with each other. Another
instance of petitio principii appears in the very next paragraph where Freud
assures us that the traumatic underpinnings of hysteria are proved by the
development of the disorder. Here, precisely the theory Freud attempts to prove
is used as evidence for itself.
(3) The
Prevalence of Childhood Sexual Abuse. Freud’s 1897 reservations about the
prevalence of childhood sexual abuse is in blatant contradiction to statements
about it in the seduction papers. In The
Aetiology of Hysteria he avers:
It seems to me certain that our children are
far more exposed to sexual assaults than the few precautions taken by parents
in this connection would lead us to expect. When I first made enquiries about
what was known on the subject, I learnt from colleagues that there are several
publications by paediatricians which stigmatize the frequency of sexual
practices by nurses and nursery maids, carried out on infants in arms; and in
the last few weeks I have come across a discussion of “Coitus in Childhood” by
Dr. Stekel (1895) in Vienna. I have not had time to collect other published
evidence; but even if it were only scanty, it is to be expected that increased
attention to the subject will very soon confirm the great frequency of sexual
experiences and sexual activity in childhood (Freud, 1896c, p. 207). (5)
Despite these assurances about the widespread
reality of the Victorian sexual abuse of children, we are asked by Freud
nineteen months later to believe his doubts about the ST were in part triggered
by his realization that such abuse was not all that prevalent. Even modern
critics like Grünbaum (1979) have accepted Freud’s 1897 reasoning that the
“preposterously high” level of sexual trauma required by the ST “over-taxed
Freud’s own belief in his seduction etiology” (Grünbaum, 1979, p.135). However,
the fancied statistical improbabilities implied by the ST was not the tale told
in 1896, and the contrast between the earlier polemic and his remarks in the
1897 Fliess correspondence is noteworthy. Perhaps Freud had good reasons for
renouncing a theory he propounded months before; but sudden awareness of
epidemiological verities was not one of them. There was nothing new in the
sociological picture of infant abuse he could have learned about in the
intervening period that would explain his revisionism. He was as sociologically
sophisticated about its prevalence in 1896 as he was in 1897. That Freud
suddenly realized the lesser extent of the abuse in 1897, but not nineteen
months earlier is difficult to swallow. Moreover, it flies in the face of the
way he marshaled evidence for the widespread nature of the problem in The Aetiology of Hysteria.
(4) The
Inability to Differentiate Between Real and Fantasized Events. In The Aetiology of Hysteria, Freud felt
that the reality of early sexual abuse as a causative factor was underscored by
the striking similarity of accounts of the eighteen patients who had been in
treatment with him up to April of 1896:
There are, however, a whole number of other
things that vouch for the reality of infantile sexual scenes. In the first
place there is the uniformity which they exhibit in certain details, which is a
necessary consequence if the preconditions of these experiences are always of
the same kind, but which would otherwise lead us to believe that there were
secret understandings between the various patients (Freud, 1896c, p. 205).
Subsequently, as we have seen, Freud
ostensibly felt no need to reconcile the similarity of reports of abuse with
the newly hypothesized pathogen, fantasized
experiences. The basis for the historical reality of seduction, the
uniformity of reports from patient to patient, was suddenly forgotten in the
flurry of enthusiasm for the power of fantasy. If, after 1897, reported
seductions were construed as imagined rather than real, what was to be made of
the uniformity of theme in patients’ disclosures that Freud leaned on earlier
to bolster a case for the actuality of the traumas? How much uniformity of
theme is to be expected in fantasized material? Ought it to be more
thematically heterogeneous than reports of actual trauma? If so, how much more?
If not, how much less?
Perhaps there is no basis for assuming that
fantasized events should be less uniform thematically than actual ones. But
Freud earlier was insistent on the idea that uniformity confirmed the reality
of trauma, whereas when switching to fantasy in 1897 he was apparently not
bothered by the issue. This is all the more surprising in the light of Freud’s
wholesale reliance on the notion of uniformity for other polemical purposes.
For example, the lack of uniformity among precipitating events of adolescence or
late childhood was used by Freud to dramatize the fact the real pathogen must
have lurked farther back in chronology (Schimek, 1987, p. 941). (7)
Preoccupations with the consistency of
thematic material is a motif showing up at many historical junctures, and in
many guises. In the sixteenth century, Thomas Erastus faulted Johann Weyer’s
theory of the falsity of witch confessions in the latter’s 1563 treatise De Praestigiis Daemonum as implausible
because their similarity from suspect
to suspect across numerous witch trials proved they were based upon real events
(Monter, 1969, p. 64). In the 1980s and 1990s, similarity of theme in reports
of ritual cult abuse became the evidential basis for their reality, even when
demons put in appearances at covens (Smith & Pazder, 1980; Stratford,
1988). “Similarity,” however, is itself an unexamined concept. When the
seventeenth century Spanish inquisitor, Alonso de Salazar y Frías, subjected
“similar” reports of satanic cult activity to more exacting scrutiny, he found
them to be a mishmash of conflicting testimony, and pronounced the affair a
gigantic hoax (Baroja, 1965; Henningsen, 1969, 1980). During the early modern
period, witches harbored grandiose goals, such as the destruction of
Christendom. Nowadays, the servants of Satan, who enjoy advance billing as
engineers of Evil, allegedly sexually molest toddlers in day care
establishments. Apparently, latter-day Satanists are either prone to
underachievement, or believe in starting small (Ebersole & Ebersole, 1993;
Sebald, 1995).
Issues pertaining to the uniformity of
clinical material played a decisive role in yet another pre-1896 controversy.
This was the wrangle over theories of hypnotism that had been waged between the
Salpêtrière School led by Charcot, and the Nancy School of Bernheim. While
critical of Charcot, Freud could not go along with Bernheim’s stress on a view
of hypnotic phenomena as mere effects of suggestibility (Freud, 1888). In his
critique of Bernheim, Freud argued that suggestibility could not account for
the uniformity of particular and
stereotyped stages of hypnosis produced by induction procedures. Freud thought
that had hypnosis been the effect of suggestion merely, its psychic, motoric,
and behavioral sequelae would have been much more varied than the stalwart
patterns Charcot reliably produced without any seeming task demands on his
subjects. It was only to emerge later that the manifestations were varied, and that the stereotypy of
Charcot’s demonstrations with hysterics were in all likelihood shaped by the
implicit task demands of the Salpêtriére context, unknown even to him
(Sulloway, 1991).
Textual
Inconsistencies
There are other paradoxes in the seduction
papers. For example, despite Freud’s references to “reports” of early seduction
by his hysterical and obsessional patients, the actual character of these
disclosures remains unclear. While a question may be raised about the
difficulty in discriminating between patient disclosures based upon actual
trauma from those based upon fantasy if Freud’s
patients reported memories of being molested as children, whether they did or
not is itself a hotly contested issue of modern scholarship. Without belaboring
the detailed exegeses of such critics as Cioffi (1972, 1974, 1988); Schimek
(1987); Macmillan (1991); Sulloway (1991); Shatzman (1992); Esterson (1993);
and Crews (1986; 1995; 1998), suffice it to say that there is ample evidence in
the canon to suggest that the founder of psychoanalysis left a rather murky
picture of his data-base for the ST. Indeed, and in line with Freud’s own
statements, what he referred to as patient “memories” of early sexual abuse may
have been reconstructions he had himself imposed on the material. Accordingly,
conceptions of the data-base on the part of modern commentators have
increasingly undergone transformations from the view that Freud’s patients
recalled intact scenes of sexual assault they disclosed to him (Masson, 1984;
Erdylei, 1984) to the view that Freud’s method involved purblind inferences to
sexual scenarios from a less than suasive trail of symptoms, nodal points, and
mental associations. (6)
The
Verbal Crucible
In his second seduction paper, Further Remarks On the Neuro-Psychoses of
Defence, Freud insists that psychoanalysis is the only method that can
unearth the true pathogen behind the psychoneuroses (Freud, 1896b, p. 164). The
implication is that it is useless to depend upon patient reports outside of
psychoanalysis to accomplish the same task. He is less than clear, however,
about whether traumas disclosed in therapy are inaccessible to consciousness
because they are only inferred from their symptomatic manifestations, or only
inaccessible outside of the analytic treatment context. The problem here
involves the aforementioned confusion over whether what Freud referred to as
“reports” of seductions were just that, or whether they were
inferences—tortuous or not—to sexual scenarios which even his patients
protested they did not remember. Be that as it may, Freud’s distrust of
anamnesis—questioning the patient as to events of the past—could hardly be said
to spring from a wholesale distrust of verbal behavior as a channel of
information. On the contrary, Freud’s approach to the latter in the seduction
papers exhibited curious levels of selectivity. Reliance on conscious
recollections was eschewed as a legitimate route to the reconstruction of the
pathogen, whereas the method of free association, while a meandering and
laborious one, was nonetheless considered to be a dependable verbal conduit to the unconscious. Yet even
here the picture is inconsistent. When a reliance on anamnesis served polemical
purposes, Freud resorted to it as if its shortcomings suddenly evaporated:
“…the aetiological pretensions of the infantile scenes rest not only on the
regularity of their appearance in the anamneses
of hysterics (Italics mine), but,
above all, on the evidence of there being associative and logical ties between
those scenes and the hysterical symptoms” (Freud, 1896c, p. 210). Ironically, Freud had been definite earlier
in the same essay that it was “useless” to depend upon anamnestic material
gleaned from outside psychoanalysis, and that it grossly distorts the
psychoanalytic procedure to describe it as involved in any such enterprise.
The probative value of free association
depends upon more than whether it is immune to the effects of “suggestion.”
Suggestibility, while a significant issue in its own right, is only one
worrisome aspect of the problem. There are several others: (2) the problem of
whether a reconstructive method mediated by free association with the effect of
suggestion controlled is an epistemologically sound way to identify pathogens,
and (3) whether the factors so identified have the causally relevant status to
begin with (Grünbaum, 1984; Erwin, 1993). With respect to (2), and even in the
absence of practitioner (i. e., Rosenthal) effects, what ensures that free
association wends an unerring way to the source of neurotic disorder? Here the
risk is not so much contamination by a response-set created by the therapeutic
relationship as much as it is a diversion of the investigative process.
Columbus might manage to cross the Atlantic with his navigational skills to be
sure, but why should he have assumed that where he landed was India? With
respect to (3), what, absenting the role of suggestion or derailment from a
proper mental spoor, guarantees that the factor unearthed is actually a
pathogen at all? Had Columbus landed in India, what made him believe he would
find there the gold to enrich Spain’s economy? Or if he found it, that there
was a sufficient supply to mine? Or, if a sufficient supply, not tucked away in
inaccessible hills? (Lourie, 1955).
Doubts about the nature of Freud’s data-base
in his originally thirteen (and subsequently, eighteen) patient caseload aside,
there are other troublesome inconsistencies in the text (Thornton, 1983;
Vetter, 1988; Israëls & Schatzman, 1993). For example, after his momentous
reversal in 1897 on the reality of the seductions, Freud subsequently reported
that one of the reasons for his newer stance on fantasy was that he hadn’t
realized in 1896 that seduction was only a necessary, not sufficient condition
for hysteria. In other words, he later denied that he had been aware of the
fact that while all hysterics were sexually abused as infants, not all
individuals so abused later developed hysteria. The statement is belied by
Freud’s comments in The Aetiology of
Hysteria, where he explicitly takes pains to emphasize his conviction that
trauma is not sufficient to produce hysteria:
Now let us turn to the other objection, which
is based precisely on an acknowledgement of the frequency of infantile
experiences and on the observed fact that many people who remember scenes of
that [early sexually traumatic] kind have not
become hysterics…It does not matter if many people experience infantile
sexual scenes without becoming hysterics, provided only that all the people who
become hysterics have experienced scenes of that kind (quoted in Masson, 1984,
pp. 269-270).
The
Identity of Perpetrators
In his later Autobiographical Study (Freud, 1925, pp. 33-35), Freud
retrospectively finds support for the so-called “father etiology” in the 1895
cases he treated with Breuer (Breuer & Freud, 1895) as well as the 1896
caseload. The “father etiology” was presumably the pathogenic effect of
paternal incest in the creation of hysteria. However, there is little in
Freud’s identification of perpetrators in his original caseloads to justify
such attributions. Accordingly, while Masson’s interpretations reflect recent
social concerns about paternal incest, no such pattern is referenced in the
original three seduction papers. In the thirteen-patient caseload of the first
of those papers, over half the perpetrators are brothers. In the last of the
papers, most perpetrators are hired servants. In addition, one stranger and two
“close relatives” are cited (Esterson, 1993).
Some critics have insisted that Freud
disguised the identity of fathers to protect Victorian family reputations.
However, the identification of seven brothers as perpetrators suggests that
maintaining veneers of social respectability was not uppermost in Freud’s mind.
Nor can this hunch explain the formulation of a “father etiology” shortly after
he took pains to protect fathers from the calumny such a theory advertises. The
“father etiology,” after all, surfaces within a year after the delivery of the
last seduction paper, as well as in the letters to Fliess. Mention of this
theory is contained in the correspondence to Fliess in the 1896 letter of 12/6,
and the 1897 letters of 1/3, 1/12, 1/24, 2/8, 4/28,/5/2, 5/31, 6/22, and 12/12
(Masson, 1985). Its introduction may have coincided with the development of
alternative theory-driven surmises.
The theory that paternal perpetrators of
incest were disguised as servants, uncles, or other relatives has been a
popular one with apologists like Gay (1988, pp. 94-95), who favor exegeses
diminishing textual inconsistencies or abrupt reversals in the canon. However,
contradictions in the Freudian oeuvre are so numerous, retrospective remarks by
the founder of psychoanalysis tend to come under a cloud. For example, in a
footnote to the 1924 edition of the Studies
in Hysteria, Freud discloses that two of his patients in the early
caseload, Katherina and Rosalia H., had each been assaulted by their
fathers—not as he originally reported, by other relatives. Katherina was
reported by Freud in 1895 to have been abused by an “uncle.” Even taking the
correction into account, the sexual episode disclosed by Katherina was not one
of infantile molestation, but unsuccessful overtures starting at the age of
fourteen by the would-be perpetrator. On one occasion the “uncle” promptly fell
asleep after invading the patient’s bed. In addition, two years later, when
Katherina was about sixteen, she merely witnessed him through a window engaging
in coitus with a cousin, Francisca. The sexual provenance of this case is
complicated by another component. Katherina’s “hallucination” of her uncle’s
face, coinciding as this did with episodes of hyperventilation, also came after
occurrences of threat and rage on the part of her uncle who felt the girl had
blown his cover with his wife who subsequently abandoned him because of
Katherina’s revelations.
Unmasking “uncles” as “fathers” may correct a
hitherto bowdlerized record—providing the true identity of the perpetrator is
thus revealed. However, the traumatic criteria Freud had outlined as
cornerstone assumptions of the ST are not met in Katherina’s case, even if the
perpetrator was her father. The required pathogenesis, a father who initiates
sexually abusive patterns in the years of a patient’s life prior to eight to
ten is, if anything, insinuated, not documented by Freud. The other possibility
is that in 1924 Freud simply forgot what he had said in 1895, putting a later
theoretical spin on his earlier discovery. Accordingly, readjustments in the
identity of perpetrators alone are not necessarily tantamount to satisfying
criteria of pathogenesis. Gay’s (1988) exegesis may be a study in irrelevance
if it is based upon such cases as Katherina’s.
Katherina aside, there is every reason to
suppose that early infantile seductions were themselves questionable
inferential constructions in Freud’s theory that adult hysteria was produced by
earlier pathogenic experiences meeting criteria of traumatic force and suitability
as determinant (Freud, 1896c).
“Force” and “suitability,” nowhere precisely defined by Freud, place
constraints on the type of event he was prepared to allow as causal in 1896
although its intended theoretical effect was to dampen explanation based upon
heritability or degeneration. In other words, to disallow that a touch, glance,
frottage, or otherwise inconsequential adolescent event has “traumatic force”
virtually precludes differential response sensitivities based upon inherent
biological vulnerability. The latter portends the role of hereditarian blight,
whereas Freud’s notions of force and suitability drew the boundaries of what
environmental events could be deemed to play a sufficient causal role in
hysteria without the complexities and variations introduced by a theory of
degeneration.
The spell of Freud’s formulations lies in his
capacity as rhetorician to convince the reader he is trotting out indisputable
clinical truths, when he is only relying on assumptions that conspire to ensure
a preordained outcome (Fish, 1986; Wilcocks, 1994). In The Aetiology of Hysteria, for example, he refers to the case of a
married couple whose “high degree of readiness to feel hurt on one occasion”
requires a background of smoldering past resentments or squabbles between them.
Freud’s reasoning here is erroneous; the sensitivity in question demands no
such assumption, since a plausible alternative hypothesis may attribute
“readiness to become hurt” to a temperamental factor ungummed from an actual
history of squabbling. Be that as it may, Freud then turns to the case of a
neurosis produced in a nubile girl by the secret stroke of a boy’s hand:
You can, of course, answer the puzzle by
pronouncing her an abnormal, eccentrically disposed and over-sensitive person;
but you will think differently when analysis shows you that the touching of her
hand reminded her of another, similar touching, which had happened very early
in her childhood… (Freud, 1896a, p. 279).
The argument is circular if in the absence of
robust evidence for the causal role of early seduction, analysis “shows” the
necessity for assuming it. Ironically, the reasoning would still be fallacious
even if such evidence were forthcoming. The assumptive causal role of early
seduction in this case would still have to be weighed against the possibility
of inherent temperamental or biogenic vulnerability, especially in light of
Freud’s assumption that seduction is a necessary, but not sufficient, condition
of hysteria. If some individuals do not later develop hysteria despite earlier
experiences meeting the “force” and “suitability as determinant” criteria, what
accounts for why individuals having similar experiences early in life can be
differentiated symptomatically later on?
Definitions
of Sexual Abuse
The Freudian notion of childhood sexual abuse
itself cries out for definition. Critics have in the main discussed Freud’s
reliance on reports of early sexual abuse in terms of whether such disclosures
could be construed as actual “reports” at all. Many have sidestepped the issue
of what sense of the term “abuse” figured as essential to the ST. Masson, in
commenting on the specific nature of the sexual scenarios, has referred to them
as “aggressive acts against…children—for seduction was an act of violence”
(Masson, 1984, p.12). The extreme nature of the acts, Masson feels, justifies
designating them as abusive, even in their least brutal form. The abusiveness,
Masson insists, is suggested by several of the leading terms Freud used to
describe the acts in question: “Verguwaltigung
(rape), Musbrauch (abuse), Verfuhrung (seduction), Angriff (attack), Attentat (assault), Aggression
(aggression), Traumen (traumas)”
(Masson, 1984, p. 3). As a general rule, other commentators tend to share
Masson’s view that the sexual events underscored by the ST were in the category
of childhood rape or molestation—with some exceptions.
At other times, Freud seemed to rely upon a
somewhat wider notion of sexual trauma than that articulated in Masson’s book,
or, indeed, in most recent commentary on the subject. This has already been
pointed out by Cioffi. This writer insists that the ST did not require any such
egregious aspect of “seductions”:
Freud’s seduction theory is not a theory of
child rape, not even in the broadest sense of sexual relations between an adult
and child. Though adults figured in an unspecified number of his patients’
seduction histories, this was not necessitated by Freud’s account of the source
of the pathogenic power of sexual arousal in childhood which lies quite simply
in its precocity. The question is not ‘What are the chances of getting through
childhood without being at the receiving end of the attentions of an adult
pervert?’ but ‘What are the chances of avoiding “doctor and nurse” games and
kindred forms of sex play with other children…I can see nothing ‘preposterous’
about the assumption that such occurrences are common enough to account for the
presumed incidence of hysteria (Cioffi, 1988, p. 62).
Cioffi claims that critics like Masson
misconstrue the ST since the theory posits the pathogenic power of sexual
arousal in childhood whatever that nature or degree of sexual stimulation
(i.e., encompassing sexual acts not unduly aggressive in character). Yet that
all or most of the seductions were in the nature of aggressive acts is apparent
in several of the descriptions Freud supplies in his eighteen patient caseload.
He mentions scenes described, inter alia,
as those of “brutal assault,” “positively revolting,” involving “all the abuses
known to debauched and impotent persons, among whom the buccal cavity and the
rectum are misused for sexual purposes” (Freud, 1896c, p. 214).
Cioffi’s minimalist theory of seduction
founders on an important point. If such sociological universals as “doctor and
nurse games” were for Freud pathogenic, the reasons for his 1897 disavowal of
the ST remain incoherent. What sense attaches to having been previously
mistaken about a preposterously high level of doctor and nurse games in
accounting for hysteria? If brutal assaults—in contrast to any kind of sexual stimulation in childhood—were not etiologically
necessary to produce later hysteria, what picture of things was Freud
repudiating in 1897? Moreover, had sexual precocity been the culprit as Cioffi
avers, even innocuous cleansing and toileting rituals might satisfy minimalist
requirements for “seduction.” Whatever Freud meant by the term, such
inconsequential daily routines seemed to be far from what he had in mind—at
least in 1896.
Perhaps problems surrounding Freud’s
definition of sexual abuse can be partially resolved by pointing out that he
may have equivocated its meaning, depending on the needs dictated by
alternative theoretical perspectives. That is, switching concepts of abuse may
explain certain incongruities in the canon. For example, in 1931 in the essay Female Sexuality, Freud asserted that
all of his earlier hysterical patients revealed that their mothers had seduced them in infancy (Freud, 1931, p. 238). Freud
characterized this patient allegation as lodged “regularly,” although pages
before in the same essay he maintains that those accused are mothers and nurses (Freud, 1931, p. 232). Far from
contradicting the father etiology, or the identity of perpetrators in the
seduction papers, the remark may only reflect a later and expanding notion of
“infantile seduction” meeting minimalist criteria of sexual abuse. At other
junctures in the canon, Freud considered “traumatic” such events as the visual
witnessing of primal scenes as in the cases of Katherina (Freud & Breuer,
1895) and the Wolf-Man (Freud, 1918). While in the seduction papers Freud
mentions the more gruesome types of sexual attack nowadays documented as all
too prevalent, other of his later comments suggest such egregious events were
only a subclass of a wider range he later considered pathogenic.
Unquestionably, there is a radical transformation in the status of the pathogen
after Freud emphasized the role of infantile fantasy, and it may be premature
to suppose that the only significant alteration in theory was the switch from
reality to fantasy. In fact, the coercive and brutal characteristics of
“seduction” cited in The Aetiology of
Hysteria all but vanished when the sexual episode was transmuted into a
figment of childhood imagination.
Even at that, the picture is not always
consistent. There seem to be changing definitions of the pathogen even within a
single theoretical time frame—and during the originary period. In Heredity and the Aetiology of the Neuroses,
there is mention of a pathogen involving “an event of passive sexuality, an
experience submitted to with indifference or with a small degree of annoyance
or fright” (Freud, 1896a, p. 155). How does such a low-keyed event comport with
our idea of infantile rape or molestation? Additionally, how is the event in
question experienced with indifference unless
it instantiates a minimalist, and looser definition of sexual abuse? We are
here torn between at least two possibilities: (1) that Freud still clung to the
notion of “trauma” as narrowly defined, i.e., a coercive or brutal event, but
opining it can on occasion be experienced indifferently
by the victim, or that (2) that Freud shifted the meaning of “trauma” to cover
sexual episodes of a far less dramatic nature. We have, in effect, two
substantially different conceptions of the pathogen: a wider one which less
often informed speculation in the seduction papers, and a more narrow one
prevailing in the seduction papers and adumbrated in, for example, current
theories of Dissociative Identity Disorder and sociological concerns about the
prevalence of childhood sexual abuse (Lynn & Rhue, 1994; Cohen, Berzoff
& Elin, 1995; Hacking, 1995). In the main, critics who have commented on
the issue have elected to argue that Freud was adhering exclusively to the
narrow (Masson) or wider (Cioffi) definition of sexual trauma. However, there
is a third possibility: slippery and alternating reliance on both senses of
“trauma,” depending upon rhetorical purpose.
Equivocating between the narrow and wider
definitions may have had a strategic purpose: permitting Freud to exit the ST
in late 1897. In the September 21, 1897 letter to Fliess, one of the reasons
Freud gave for abandoning the ST was the unlikelihood of such widespread
perversions by fathers—as if fathers had ever originally been cited as
predators! Under the looser definition of trauma, of course, such “perversions”
need not have been the restricted playing field in establishing ST surmises.
Ironically, suspecting a connection between
infantile sexual episodes and later symptoms, far from being a Freudian
innovation, was endemic in Victorian medical theorizing.7
In Heredity and the Aetiology of the Neuroses,
Freud himself acknowledges that “Sexual disorders have always been admitted
among the causes of nervous illness, “ although “subordinated to heredity”
(Freud, 1896a, p. 149). During 1885 and before, fully a decade before Freud’s
ST, Henoch, Cohn, Schaefer, and Herz all argued that that if infantile sexual
episodes caused neurosis, the latter were more widespread than observed
(Carter, 1983). This was the very same argument Freud relied on in 1897 when
rejecting the ST. Under the looser definition of abuse, however, widespread
“trauma” in children is not only not rare, it is virtually inevitable, and
authored by a social cast of characters far more varied than fathers. As was
mentioned, the wider notion also embraces phenomena we would refrain from
classifying as “perverse” or abusive.” (8)
Sidestepping
Heredity
Returning to the other thematic emphasis in
the seduction papers, we note that in Heredity
and the Etiology of the Neuroses, the term heredity or its cognates is referenced about thirty-six times. The
invisible grip that the Victorian glossing of this concept had on the founder
of psychoanalysis in the originary decade and beyond remains to be clarified.
Freud’s ST, whatever else it represents as a landmark contribution to trauma
theory, was also a cryptic expression of its author’s need to circumvent
attributing the neuroses to biogenic, particularly hereditarian, factors. The
subtext of degeneration in the ST becomes more apparent when we see it as an
aspect of Freud’s campaign to rescue the psychoneuroses from the aura of
immutability cast by hereditarian doctrine.
Far from restricting himself to symptomatic
patterns for which the notion of repression played a key role, Freud also
supplied environmentalist accounts of the actual neuroses. These were
subdivided into neurasthenia and the anxiety neuroses. The former embraced a
pattern of debilitation and energy depletion (specifically, “fatigue,
intra-cranial pressure, flatulent dyspepsia, constipation, spinal parasthesias,
sexual weakness, etc. (Freud, 1896a, p. 150) traceable to patterns of masturbation,
or depletion of the sexual factor. The other was the anxiety neuroses (Zwangsneurose), patterns roughly
coextensive with what nowadays might be diagnosed as generalized anxiety
disorder, panic disorder, simple phobia, post-traumatic stress disorder, or
adjustment disorder with anxious mood (for Freud, irritability, states of
anxious expectation, phobias, anxiety attacks, complete or rudimentary, attacks
of fear and vertigo, tremors, sweating, congestion, dyspnea, tachycardia, etc.,
chronic diarrhea, chronic locomotor vertigo, hyperaesthesia, insomnia, etc.),
the pathogen for which was frustration of the sexual factor, as in coitus interruptus, “enforced
abstinence, unconsummated genital excitation…sexual efforts which exceed the
subject’s psychical capacity, etc.” (Freud, 1896a, pp. 150-151).
Much is made of the fact that the reception
accorded the seduction papers on the part of the medical community was a
hostile one—as though Freud delivered his address to a medical community
unprepared to receive discoveries in advance of their time. On the contrary,
Freud would have never had the temerity to present what in terms of modern
medicine constitutes junk science had not his peers been already partially
receptive to a linkage between sexuality and neurotic disorder. Kraft-Ebbing’s
comment about Freud’s ST that it “sounded like a scientific fairy-tale” (“Es klingt wie ein wissenschaftliches
Märchen”) was in all likelihood prompted by the convoluted explanations of
its author, not by the idea of a connection between sexual events and later
neurotic disturbance simpliciter, a
linkage many Victorian physicians already held as established.
Freud’s attitude towards heredity was not
always of a piece. It underwent several distinct changes in the originary period.
The hereditarian cast to speculation over psychiatric conditions was rife in
Victorian academic and medical theorizing, and Freud, like many of his
contemporaries, originally endorsed heredity as a primary pathogen. The trend
was especially discernable in the early days of his sojourn at Salpêtrière,
under Charcot’s influence. In 1888 he claimed that hysteria was hereditary,
sexual factors being of secondary importance:
The etiology of the status hystericus is to be looked for entirely in heredity…Compared
with the factor of heredity all other factors take a second place and play the
part of incidental causes, the importance of which is as a rule overrated in
practice (Freud, 1888, p. 50).
Freud’s earlier endorsement of Charcot’s
genetic position on the etiology of hysteria was backed up by seemingly
persuasive arguments. He stressed the fact that hysteria, while inherited,
could not be attributed to anatomical abnormalities of the sexual organs. Here,
he countered that the condition occurred in sexually immature individuals,
women with a complete lack of genitalia, and women who have diseases of the
sexual organs who nonetheless do not suffer from hysteria.
Freud’s French Connection
Before his
traveling bursary stipend was awarded by the Viennese medical Society, Freud
looked forward to his Parisian trip in order to familiarize himself with a
broader spectrum of pediatric cerebral pathology (Freud 1886a, p. 8). Attending
Charcot’s Monday and Tuesday lectures, the consultation
extreme, he was privy to case presentations of challenging and puzzling
clinical phenomena, including hysteria. In his 1886 summary of his experiences,
Freud placed double emphasis on Charcot’s contribution to the study of
hysteria, namely: (1) emphasizing the disorder as a true medical condition,
rather than a factitious one, i.e., one that had come to be regarded in
traditional medical circles as simulation or malingering; and (2) codifying the
somatic signs and stages of hysteria, stigmata that cropped up more frequently
than hitherto assumed.
Szasz (1961)
has argued that the switch from “malingering” to “hysteria” or “medical
disorder” was a conceptual one not based upon purely empirical considerations.
True, there were characteristic features of hysterical patterns both Charcot
and Freud catalogued, and the decision to classify them as “sickness” rather
than “dissembling” or “malingering” may be likened to certain judicial rulings in contrast to purely
empirical discoveries. Szasz concludes on this basis that the switch was illicit
because it was driven by the purchasing of a newer social role commanding
sympathetic treatment as “disease” at the expense of a falsehood. However, the
sympathetic social role can as readily be seen as a consequence of diagnosing
“disorder,” rather than as a motivation for engineering the reclassification.
Furthermore, saying that hysterics should be accorded a social role more
commensurate with “faking” than “being sick” was in the past also a move in a
language-game requiring its own validation. (Is the original classification of
“typhoid fever, and carcinomas and fractures” as “illnesses” illicit because of
the essential dissimilarities among these phenomena?) According to Szsaz, what
are the “scientific observations or logical arguments” for categorizing
hysteria as malingering historically,
and prior to Charcot’s newfangled reclassification as disorder, given the essential differences between ordinary cases of
malingering (i.e., without the quasi-neurological overlay) and “hysteria”?
Freud’s attitude toward the French
neurologist was one of an admiring student. He was enthralled by his
instructor’s command of the subject matter and his spellbinding lectures. As a
result, Freud in 1886 (Freud, 1886b) was inspired to author a German
translation of Charcot’s work, Neue
Vorlessungen uber die Krankheiten des Nervensystems insbesondre uber Hysterie (New
Lectures On the Diseases of the Nervous System, including Hysteria), not to
mention another article appearing in French in Archives de Neurologie in 1893. In his Charcot paper of 1893
(Freud, 1893), Freud draws a parallel between hysteria and cases of witchcraft
and demon possession during the Middle Ages, phenomena he was later to explore
in his 1922 paper A Seventeenth Century
Demonological Neurosis, as well as in letters to Fliess of January 17 and
24 (Masson, 1985, pp. 224-228).
Nothing in Freud’s Paris report of 1886 gives
indication that there was more to the panegyric he accorded his teacher than
meets the eye—but there was. In August of 1893, well before the publication of
the ST, Freud authored another essay, Charcot,
which diplomatically explored the weaknesses of his former teacher’s views on
hysteria. While extolling Charcot’s restoring “dignity to the topic” (Freud,
1893, p. 19), Freud proceeds to probe the essential weakness of his teacher’s
position. This for Freud consisted in Charcot’s insistence on hysteria being a
form of hereditary degeneracy, a subclass of famille nèvropathique (Féré, 1884). On this theory, other pathogens
are relegated to the minor category of agents
provocateurs, mere triggering factors atop the real vulnerability.
Freud’s objection to Charcot’s theory is
discernable in the last paragraph of Charcot.
The formulation informed by genetic taint, Freud declares, “will no doubt
require sifting and amending” (Freud, 1893, p.23). the reason for this is that
“so greatly did Charcot overestimate heredity as a causative agent that he left
no room for the acquisition of nervous illness…nor did he make a sufficiently
sharp distinction between organic nervous affections and neuroses, either as
regards their etiology or in other aspects” (Freud, 1893, p. 23). Then, as in
all elegies in which trotting out the limitations of the deceased requires the
expression of compensatory sentiments lest one be perceived as kicking the
corpse, Freud appends the diplomatic:
It is inevitable that the advance of our
science, as it increases our knowledge, must at the same time lessen the value
of a number of things that Charcot taught us; but neither changing times nor
changing views can diminish the name of the man whom—in France and elsewhere—we
are mourning today (Freud, 1893, p. 23).
Charcot’s influence on Freud is discernable
in the importation of ideas surfacing later in the seduction papers, especially
Heredity and the Aetiology of the
Neuroses. For example, Charcot’s distinction between traumatic and organic
paralysis was transformed into the Freudian distinction between the origins of
hysteria and hereditary disorder. The independence of hysteria from
practitioner effects mirrors the position adopted by Charcot in his controversy
with Bernheim on the subject of hypnotic induction as a neurological tool
versus an effect of suggestibility. Finally, the phrase agents provocateurs in The
Aetiology of Hysteria was not only borrowed from the Charcot lexicon, but
given a meaning that clashed with the one honored by the French neurologist.
For Charcot, agents provocateurs were
environmental triggers producing clinical patterns in genetically compromised
organisms; for Freud, they became the accidental triggers in later
chronological development betraying the existence of precocious sexual
experience amounting to environmentally sourced trauma. The appropriation of
concepts and terminology from Charcot in the service of a psychological theory
wholly contrary to the Frenchman’s theoretical intent is not mere speculation;
Freud explicitly makes such an attribution (Freud 1896a, p. 155).
In 1888 Freud reserved a minor functional
role for sexuality in the origins of hysteria as a concession to the “high
psychical significance” of this factor in all kinds of neurosis (Freud, 1888,
pp. 50-51; Levin, 1944, pp. 123-124). The second phase of his thinking,
beginning with the transitional period of 1892 to 1893, involved recognition of
a less dramatic influence of heredity as a contributing factor, as when, in
Draft A Freud relegated its influence to the status of a “multiplier” (Stewart,
1976). Freud referenced the potentiating effect of heredity, like that of an electrical
circuit, even in the first seduction paper Heredity
and the Problem of the Neuroses (Freud, 1896a, p. 147). Diminishing its role was more apparent in the last of the three
papers, The Aetiology of Hysteria. This
paper argues that the infantile sexual episode preempted a more dominant role
for heritability. However, Freud’s final position in this paper equivocated on
the issue of just how secondary a factor heredity was. For example, Freud
insisted that “pseudo-heredity,” a lineage of family neuroses springing from
seductions, could get masked as a biogenic transmission of traits. The actual
role of the latter variable uncomplicated by psychosocial factors was left
indeterminate.
The
Medicalization of Race
Freud’s sojourn in Paris at the Salpêtrière
from October 1885 to February 1886 coincided with a period of anti-Semitic
ferment in France (Stewart, 1976; Gilman, 1993a). The failure of the Catholic
bank, the Union Generale in 1882, was
blamed on the Jews in general and Rothschild influence in particular (Stewart,
1976; Weber, 1986). There were several contemporaneous trials of Jews for
ritual murder. Edouard Drumont’s inflammatory La France juiv, a diatribe against Jewish influence on national
affairs, enjoyed popularity (Stewart, 1976). The Dreyfus affair, a scandal that
drove a deep cleavage between French factions convinced that no less than the
honor of the country was at stake, was fulminating. Dreyfusards like Emile Zola
began clamoring for redress around the time the ST was formulated and abandoned.
French intolerance in this period of ferment had a distinctly racial cast when
it came to Jews, although flagrant episodes of open violence against Italian
immigrants was sparked by economic motives purely (Weber, 1986, pp. 134-135).
The influx of Jewish immigrants from Eastern Europe sparked fears of racial
taint and degeneration through intermarriage with them. This social anxiety was
expressed indirectly in a British literary metaphor: Bram Stoker’s Dracula. Its principal character is a
scourge from the Slavic (Romanian) East. He turns his victims into one of his
own kind by draining their blood or exchanging it with his own. (9)
One year before Freud’s stay in Paris, in
1884, Charles Féré had developed the notion of famille névropathique (Féré, 1884), underscoring a lineage
involving the hereditary predisposition to nervous disease. In 1894, two years
before Freud’s ST, he traced several cases of hysteria to early sexual
molestation, but with a difference: Féré did not feel repression played any role
in the etiology of the condition.
The idea of hereditary predisposition in
Victorian thinking was linked to the medicalization of race. High on the list
of groups vulnerable to the blights of hereditary taint were Jews. Racial
theorists of nineteenth century Europe, including Freud’s idol Jean-Marie
Charcot, considered Jews and Asiatics particularly at risk. Latter day pundits,
like Murray and Herrnstein in The Bell
Curve place them at the top—at least as far as I.Q. is concerned (Murray
& Herrnstein, 1994). Consistency was never a strong card in racial
theorizing.
Heated debates over degenerative gene pools
were quite the rage in Victorian Europe. They captured the imagination of many
medical theorists, including Charles Darwin’s cousin, Sir Frances Galton,
Alsberg, Binswanger, Budul, Siebert, Pilcz, Kirchhof, Buschan, Burgle,
Wulfing-Luer, Leroy-Beaulieu, Ziemssen, Löwenfeld, Erb, Krafft-Ebing, Gutmann,
Kraepelin, Frigyes, and Charcot (Gilman, 1993a, pp. 93-168). While the
rudimentary European sociological literature did not document a relatively
greater incidence of brother-sister incest among Jews, the common Victorian
assumption was that they were more susceptible to such patterns because of
their degenerated blood lines. Alleging brother-sister incest among Jews was
ironic. The Aryan crown-prince of racial purity, Siegfried, was himself the
product of an incestuous union: Siegmund and Sieglinde. Seven cases of
brother-sister incest crop up in Freud’s original caseload. Many of these
patients were Jewish, while Thomas Mann’s novella Blood of the Walsungs is the story of a Jewish incestuous pair by
the names of Siegmund and Sieglinde (Gilman, 1993b, p. 178).
Freud references hereditarian doctrine many
times in the seduction papers of 1896. In
Further Remarks On the Neuro-Psychoses of Defence, and at the end of its
first section, Freud declares; “How greatly the claims of hereditary
disposition are diminished by the establishment in this way of [environmental]
aetiological factors as a determinant needs no more than a mention” (Freud,
1896b, p. 163). The conclusion is fallacious. Freud’s view of the inconsistency
between the ST and a theory of genetic predisposition was not only specious; it
was promoted on the basis of data he amassed at break-neck speed. The first
seduction paper relied on a cohort of thirteen patients. Since it was sent off
to the publisher on February fifth, and Freud reported data on eighteen
patients on April twenty-first of the same year, it appears he was able to
determine the requisite etiology of five new cases in the amazing time of two
and a half months, or seventy-five days. Considering the fact that he
characterized his procedures as “laborious” on the first occasion he coined the
term “psychoanalysis,” it is astonishing that five cases yielded up their
secrets—if they did this—with such alacrity. The idea that hereditary
predisposition as an etiological factor is diminished in likelihood because
Freud outlined specific events in the life history of patients to account for
later neurosis is a non sequitur,
especially in light of his insistence that not all sexually abused children
become hysterics subsequently. Cannot temperamental differences among
individuals with a genetic predisposition also account for the morbidity?
In Heredity
and the Aetiology of the Neuroses, Freud announces that the ST undercuts
the role of heredity by recruiting the notion of “accidental factors” in the
life span. By “accidental factors” he means those precocious sexual events that
were environmentally induced, not an aspect of native endowment, or traits
templated in the germplasm.
Why was Freud so motivated to dispute the
hereditarian stance, and so eager to develop a purely psychological theory to
explain neuroses? While Sulloway (1992) has argued persuasively that Freud’s
system was an extension of the nineteenth century biology in which he was
trained, there is another side to the story. Moreover, grounding in biological
science does not account for Freud’s attraction to crackpot theories such as
Fliess’s biorhythms, nasal determinism, or his preoccupation with numerology
(as this relates to the occult significance of addresses and telephone numbers,
not to mention intimations of his own death). Even as staunch a loyalist as Gay
felt that Freud should have been more skeptical of Fliess’s “dogmatism” and
“obsessions,” not to mention the latter’s “high-flying attempt to ground
biology in mathematics” (Gay, 1988, p. 57).
Freud’s environmentalism may have been his
version of coming to grips with nineteenth century racial theory condemning
Jews to degenerative blood lines. In fact, this subtext had personal and
specific meaning for him. Shortly after his endorsement of Charcot’s views on
the genetic basis for hysteria, Freud had occasion to remind himself of the
“neuropathic taint” among members of his own family tree, observing that such
“stories are very common in Jewish families” (Freud, 1964, p. 203). In his
February 11, 1897 letter to Fliess, Freud drew attention to his discovery of
hysteria in several of his siblings, and in the letters of August 14 and
October 3 of the same year cites the discovery of the condition in himself. To
racial theorists, of course, such “discoveries” were hardly revelations when it
came to Jews! McGrath notes that the increasingly anti-Semitic ambience of the
late nineteenth century European French and German scene may have been the
backdrop that motivated Freud to counter with an environmentalist, not
hereditarian take on the neuroses (McGrath, 1986, p. 161).
Was Freud’s perception of hysteria in his
nuclear family for him an alarming confirmation of Victorian racial theory—so
alarming it was necessary for him to theorize it away? Some authors (Balmary,
1979; Krüll, 1979) have dwelt on the fate of the ST during the originary period
as this relates to the theme of Freud’s relationship with his father. What such
a focus may ignore, however, is the extent to which Jacob Freud’s imputed
“perversity” may have been a forced move (and eventually a reductio ad absurdum) in a formulation originally framed as an
alternative to racial doctrine. In short, an implication of the ST was that if
Freud’s family members were “hysterics,” then their condition was the effect of
an older sex abuser in the nuclear family configuration. Why the culprit had to
be Jacob (rather than the mother, brothers, servants, or family relatives or
nursemaids) probably stems from the vagaries of Freud’s finger-pointing .
Victorian theories of Jewish degeneration, as
were mentioned, were driven by medical notions of hereditary taint. Considering
this, it would have been impossible for Freud to have considered the idea of
genetic transmission ungummed from self-incrimination. If, however, heredity
was nothing but repressed sexual molestation, then neuroses were created because of what happened to people, not because
of their native endowment. This theme registered in nineteenth century
treatises of European Jewish physicians. In an all too apparent defensive mode,
many of them argued that the presumed higher percentage of neurosis among Jews
reflected their adverse social circumstances and struggles in prejudiced
communities, not the biological consequences of degeneration (Fishberg, 1911).
Politics
and Paranoia
The relationship between an enduring, but
often “civilized” Viennese anti-Semitism, and Freud’s presumed hypersensitivity
about this is another intriguing issue. What, it may be asked, is a “normal,”
not “hypersensitive” response to such a Weltanschauung?
The force of the term “hypersensitive” smacks of deviancy of reaction, while
the assumed boundaries of non-pathological reactivity to racial prejudice
remains a murky determination. We know that Freud felt increasingly isolated
from the medical establishment. If this was in part sparked by its implicit
hostility to Jews, what should the proper Jewish response have been?
A critical consensus has it that despite the
intolerance of Viennese society to ethnic difference—an intolerance as
instanced by its tacit acceptance of fin
de siecle racial theories of Jewish degeneration and extended to persons of
color and Asiatic descent (Gilman, 1993a)—Freud’s personal attitude toward the
establishment was uniquely stamped in the form of a personality quirk.
Accordingly, critics seek to psychiatricize Freud’s attitude toward his social
milieu, a textual stance they feel is confirmed by what Esterson has called
Freud’s “paranoia” (Esterson, 1993, p.130). The problem here is that the trait
in question was manifested in a society in which Jews were already derogated.
In such an atmosphere, who establishes the permissible boundaries of antipathy
or normalcy of response? When one is the target of such pressure, just what
attitude is the acceptable one, and according to whose standards?
As a questionable case in point of Freud’s
“paranoia” (Farrell, 1996), let us consider the 1897 episode of his belated
appointment as Extraordinarius (i.e.,
Associate Professor) to the faculty of the University of Vienna. Freud’s
candidacy was recommended by both Nothnagel and Krafft-Ebing in January of that
year, and in June by the academic assembly of the university. Von Hartel, the
Minister of Education, temporized on recommending appointment until February
27, 1902. It was finally endorsed by Emperor Franz Joseph on March 11, 1902,
fully five years after it was received by the ministry. Moreover, it was not
until the intervention of well-placed patients and after the request was
renewed by sponsors that it was finally ratified. Freud was also informed by
his instructor Sigmund Exner in 1902 that there was a move afoot to abort the
nomination. Freud had written Fliess on February 8, 1897 he had been warned by
his sponsors that there may be forces at work intent on sabotaging the
appointment. The subsequent controversy over whether anti-Semitism played any role
in delaying Freud’s appointment is perhaps studded with more complexities than
recent critics allow.
Ellenberger (1970), Sulloway (1992), and
Glicklhorn and Glicklhorn (1960) have insisted that anti-Semitism did not
motivate the delay, although this was Freud’s perception. Ellenberger feels
that Freud was neither “really isolated” nor “ill-treated” by colleagues
(Ellenberger, 1970, p.448) while Sulloway argues that seven of the ten 1897
candidates in Freud’s group were Jewish and that von Hartel was down on record
as denouncing anti-Semitism. However, as McGrath (1986) points out, the
administrative quota on promotions might have been put in place explicitly to
offset the number of Jews rising through the academic ranks. The possibility of
some such tacit policy is suggested by the tumultuous political events
occurring during this period of Austrian history. Partial support to Kasimir
Badeni’s coalition government was given by the anti-Semitic Christian Socials,
a party responsible for the 1895 election of the racist demagogue Karl Lueger
as mayor of Vienna. It is plausible to suppose that the coalition was perceived
as being made more fragile by concessions to Jews at governmental levels.
Quotas on academic promotions—especially in cases in which seventy per cent of
candidates were Jewish—would have effectively diminished opportunities for
anti-Semites to rabble-rouse around local issues.
Whatever the true picture behind Freud’s
appointment delay, his alleged “paranoia” about the promotion hinges on the outcome
of a political analysis of some complexity. Thus, had the quota actually been
established on anti-Semitic grounds, Freud’s “paranoia” begins to look more
like political astuteness. The upshot of another way of looking at such events
is to query how much “paranoia” over anti-Semitism is really paranoia in an
anti-Semitic environment? This in no way diminishes the possibility of
personality factors entering the equation, although separating reality from
paranoid distortion may not be as easy as some suppose.
Similar considerations apply to Ellenberger’s
denial of “ill treatment” of Freud at the hands of his colleagues. A case in
point is the Salpêtrière sojourn. Charcot’s treatment of Freud was in many
respects collegial—even to the point of permitting his student to translate his
works. Yet what should have been Freud’s attitude toward a mentor who believed
on theory his student was at risk for being a racial degenerate? It is, of
course, quite in the style of conventional wisdom everywhere to fashion its own
criteria of mistreatment—to which those on the receiving end are expected to
adhere.
Quashing heredity for Freud took yet another
form: construing it as a farrago of fixed and acquired characteristics. Thus,
Freud’s Lamarckian assumptions concerning inheritance implied that racial
characteristics passed along through the germplasm themselves originated in the
experiences of one’s ancestors. Translated into terms compatible with a
doctrine of the susceptibility of Jews to psychological disorder, this meant
that what was passed along was still in the nature of what happened to people, not what they were intrinsically. Freud’s forays into the generational
transmission of traits, memories, and melodramas, as in Totem and Taboo (Freud, 1912-1913, pp. 1-161) were probably
partially driven by the need to explain the origins of similar infantile
fantasies. For if after 1897 he came to regard seduction fantasies as scenarios
ungrounded in reality and springing from the Oedipal conflict, why was the
scenario always the same, and what was the provenance of its singular thematic
material? Here Lamarckianism also came to the rescue. True, the theme of
killing the father and sexually possessing the mother is inherited to be sure,
but not from flatfooted chromosomes. It derives from the experiences of one’s ancestors who in the distant past were caught
up in real life Oedipal dramas
Freud, like so many of his contemporaries,
both Jew and Gentile, was so taken with the alleged epidemiological realities
upon which racial theory depended, his strategy for self-redemption developed
within the constraints it imposed. The strategy became one of rescuing the
vulnerability thought to be a statistically high risk for Jews, neurosis, from
the purview of genetic blight. Achieving this meant showing how the blight in
question was freed from an aura of inevitability by being stamped with
environmentally wrought characteristics. The theoretical adjustments necessary
to get out from under the depredations of racial theory amounted to quite a
two-step by Freud. But his failure to fashion a plausible alternative for
self-redemption must be considered in the light of his feeling downgraded.
Unlike contemporary social and biological
scientists (Gould, 1981), Freud was in no position to attack racial theory
directly. The latter was an intellectual tradition so ingrained in the medical
thinking of his era, opposing its statistics on the prevalence of Jewish mental
disorder would have been akin to bowdlerizing anatomy or reversing knowledge about
infectious diseases. Racial theory had—and still has—another unique
characteristic. It tends to color thinking about ethnicity by instilling
attitudes that linger long after their open expression has been rendered
anachronistic by updated knowledge. When current dictates of diplomacy,
manners, or tact forbid the overt expression of racially inspired sentiment,
the invisibly harbored doctrines can persevere as strongly as ever.
Endnotes
(1) The British philosopher J. L. Austin (Austin, 1960)
undertook to discuss “trouser words.”
These are words like “real” whose negative usage “not real” or “unreal”
give the trouser word its definite sense. It is one of the purposes of this
paper to argue that Freud’s tacit preoccupation with the idea of degeneration
was the trouser aspect of his seduction theory. Infantile sexual abuse,
accordingly, was the manifest theme of the seduction papers, but it was degeneration that wore the pants.
(2) Esterson (1993, pp. 14-15) and others fix the period
at 18 months, one month less than the period between the delivery of The Aetiology of Hysteria and the letter
to Fliess of September 21, 1897.
(3) By and large, the connection between theory and
therapeutic effectiveness is nowadays played down by Freudian loyalists who
have sought to unglue the psychoanalytic theoretical edifice from the
effectiveness of psychoanalytic therapy. In line with this, Sachs (1989)
disputes Grünbaum’s contention that “attribution of therapeutic success to the undoing of repressions—rather than to
mere suggestion—was the foundation, both logically and historically, for the
central dynamical significance that unconscious ideation acquired in
psychoanalytic theory: without the reliance on the presumed dynamics of their therapeutic results, Breuer and
Freud could have never propelled clinical data into repression etiologies”
(Grünbaum, 1984, p. 182). Sachs faults Grünbaum for ignoring Freud’s argument
that analytic assumptions are confirmed through parallels between the findings
in neuroses and cases of paranoia and dementia
praecox (schizophrenia), which are untreatable and impervious to the
effects of suggestion.
Sachs may
be wrong on several counts. First, Grünbaum in due course discusses at least
three different senses of “linkage” in which the connection between
psychoanalytic theory and therapy come into play (Grünbaum, 1991). Second, when
the treatment of paranoia met theoretical needs of the moment in 1896, Freud
was far from pessimistic about the therapeutic outlook for psychotic cases. He
even produced a paranoid “cure” in the case of Frau P.—subject, of course, to
whatever claims of clinical regression in this patient he found it convenient
to posit in later revisions of theory. Third, there is an incongruity between
there being virtually no psychotic patients in Freud’s caseload and his
maintaining that the “translation of symbols and the phantasies” of psychosis
“coincides faithfully” with the data produced in neurotic cases. This
conclusion, derivable only on the basis of the requisite psychoanalytic
procedures in the consulting room, was evidently drawn without a sufficient
enough number of psychotic patients in the caseload to establish its
credibility. Fourth, there is an inconsistency between a dearth of such
patients and Freud’s pronouncement that such patients are not vulnerable to suggestion.
Erwin (1993) has addressed the
question of the alleged imperviousness of psychotics to suggestion, arguing
that the research literature would seem to indicate otherwise. However, a share
of Erwin’s evidence involves confirmation of the “suggestibility factor” in
operant studies embracing verbal conditioning and instrumental behaviors
(Krasner, 1958; Ayllon & Haughton, 1964; Salzinger & Pisoni, 1961). A
question arises here about the relevance of operant conditioning studies to
Freud’s notion of “suggestibility.” Thus, to assert that a patient’s behavior
has been modified by reinforcement does not imply that the resultant patterns
have been created through the effect of “suggestion,” even if the latter
concept is blurry. In the experimental analysis of behavior, suggestion effects
may be construed as the by-products of reinforced patterns, but the converse
does not hold. A pattern is not indisputably the effect of “suggestion,” merely
because it was reinforced, just as the tendency for laboratory planaria to turn
right at a choice point in a maze is a result of suggestion simply because they
were reinforced for doing so. Consequently, neither must human subjects
reinforced in analogous ways acquire their patterns through “suggestion.”
Erwin’s example of a schizophrenic woman reinforced for carrying a broom in the
Ayllon, Haughton & Hughes (1965) study does not seem to capture the notion
of a pattern created through suggestion; it only illustrates the case of a
patient for whom a chosen psychoanalytic interpretation is doubtful when it
transpires psychologists have been reinforcing broom-carrying patterns. The
behavior in question did not necessarily originate
because broom-carrying was suggested by experimenters. I say “not necessarily”
because suggestion is not altogether ruled out either; but neither is it
guaranteed. Despite the possible irrelevance of operant strategies to the issue
of suggestion, Freud nonetheless had little justification for making his
exclusionary remarks, especially in the light of his limited access to this
patient population.
Lastly,
on what basis did Freud contend psychotics are impervious to suggestion in the
context of his 1909 dismissal of “suggestibility” as a “catchword,” not to
mention its lack of clear definition? Impervious to what? Evidently, the
conceptual laxity Freud is permitted by loyalists is off limits to critics like
Grünbaum. Sachs (1989, p. 355) takes Grünbaum to task for the latter’s fuzzy
notion of “suggestion,” while Erwin (1993) is forced to grapple with several
senses of the term in order to cover all the possibilities of meaning spawned
by its ambiguity. Ironically, Sachs seems more impatient with Grünbaum’s
failure to clarify the meaning of “suggestibility” when criticizing Freud, than
he is with the latter for failing to do likewise in his critique of Berheim’s
theory of suggestibility in hypnotism (Freud, 1888; Ellenberger, 1970; Sulloway,
1992).
The
theory/therapy marriage is indisputable in the seduction papers, whatever the
looseness of the connection in post-1987 theorizing. Despite this, modern
theorists who wish to disengage psychoanalytic theory from the support given to
it by therapeutic effects must grapple with the larger issue of justifying the
system. Loyalists cannot maintain there is something worthwhile about
psychoanalytic theory unwed from those therapeutic effects and explanatory
virtues serving to distinguish it over rival theoretical accounts. If a
putative recovery of a repressed “memory” fails to ameliorate symptoms any
better than alternative approaches, what is the evidential basis for contending
the pathogen is a memory, whether of
an actual or fantasized event? True, the theory may receive confirmation in
other areas of inquiry, like experimental or epidemiological investigations.
However, support for it from these quarters, while occasionally suggestive, is
in the main equivocal or poor.
The point
here should not be misconstrued. It is not that psychoanalytic theory is
necessarily vacuous unless
psychoanalysis can be shown to be therapeutically sound or superior; it is only
that in the absence of differential treatment results, what is to recommend it,
given the existence of equally effective—and less lengthy or
expensive!—treatment alternatives? If this is crassly pragmatic, so be it.
(4) Freud’s “hysteria,” as defined in his paper Hysteria cuts across several diagnostic
categories listed in the DSM-IV, the current official manual of psychiatry
nosology (American Psychiatric Association, 1994). The constellation of
clinical disturbances observed by Breuer and Freud in 1895 may have represented
time-bound Victorian syndromes (Sulloway, 1992, p. 59) or “culture-bound
syndromes” (Simons & Hughes, 1985). Webster (1966) has indicated that
“hysteria” functioned as a “diagnostic dustbin,” embracing conditions that from
a modern psychiatric perspective are quite distinct. For example, the patients
in Freud and Breuer’s Studies in Hysteria,
manifest symptoms across a range of disabilities, including conversion
disorder, dissociative disorder, post-traumatic stress disorder, generalized
anxiety disorder, obsessive-compulsive disorder, amnestic syndrome, brief reactive
psychoses, etc. Complicating the diagnosis of “hysteria” is the promotion of an
illusory purview for psychogenesis,
based as it may be on premature calculation. The conviction that a condition
must be a purely “functional” or “non-organic” one—in the sense it lacks a
physiological underpinning—may have fostered misdiagnoses. Symptoms of
“hysteria” may spring from organic disorders that are unclassifiable due to the
unavailability of relevant diagnostic procedures during a given era. If
“hysterical” is medical shorthand for disturbances of function that cannot be
readily attributed to known neuropathological processes, it does not follow
that psychogenesis is the forced alternative. As Webster observes, the
etiological bases for such cases still remains an open question.
In a more comprehensive sense, there is no category of
pathology theoretically exempt from neurophysiological causation, since all
behavior, normal or otherwise, is mediated by the central nervous system. If
so, “organic” and “psychogenic” simply denote distinguishable realms of
disorder that are ultimately physical: those that have (or may come to have)
specifiable etiologies and those that do not (or will not). For what is the
alternative? A purely “mental” etiology without causal physical underpinnings,
as under Cartesian dualism? Even Freud, who surmised that all psychic processes
would eventually be described in physical terms, implied that there is no such
thing as a purely “psychic” disorder. Accordingly, the conjecture by Bowlby (2004)
that “Breuer and Freud’s initial insight that hysterical symptoms represent not
a chemical imbalance but a mental conflict” may involve a category mistake
(Ryle, 1949).
In line with the foregoing, the possible problems of a
diagnosis of “hysteria” are at least four in number: (1) it may cover a protean
variety of symptoms as to be virtually meaningless as a classificatory tool;
(2) it may refer to symptoms springing from a known neurological disorder like torsion dystonia, yet get
misdiagnosed by psychiatrists overlooking an organic basis all too familiar to
neurologists; (3) it may cover symptomatic pictures of physical conditions
unknown to all practitioners in a
given era; and (4) it may necessarily and
ultimately pertain to neurophysiological anomalies in accordance with
assumptions central to a philosophical position on the mind-body relationship
(i.e., identity theory).
(5) In referring
the putatively high level of childhood sexual abuse required by the ST, Freud
emphasized that it did not correspond quantitatively to the incidence of the
disorder, hysteria, attributed to it. The abuse had to be greater than the
prevalence of hysteria, since the latter is the delayed consequence of the
abuse. Consequently, more abuse was being perpetrated than its symptomatic
manifestations indicated, since the latter were only the accumulated results
over time.
(7) Schimek (1987) was among the first to call into
question whether Freud’s patients actually disclosed early sexual abuse.
However, he finesses his psychoanalytic stand by attempting to diminish the
significance of Freud’s switch from reality to fantasy of abuse. In this
connection he writes: “…actual seduction in early childhood played only a
limited, though indispensable role in the complex and lengthy process of
symptom formation. This early trauma was significant only to the extent that
its unconscious memory had a ‘delayed’ action at puberty…It is only when the
unconscious memory has acquired a new meaning in a different context at a later
age that it becomes a psychic trauma. Internal psychological processes and
transformations already play a central role in the seduction theory. Thus
Freud’s later shift of emphasis from reproductions of real events to fantasies
(which contain fragments of actual past experience) did not represent such a
radical break in the continuity of his thought” (Schimek, 1987, p.939). On the
other hand, and despite Schimek’s valiant effort to establish continuity of
Freud’s thought in the landmark reversal of 1897, what more important
difference can you have than the one between reality and fantasy?
(6) Sulloway (1992) may have exaggerated the originality
of key figures of Freud’s circle, like Wilhelm Fliess. In developing his thesis
that the latter’s influence on Freud has been generally underestimated,
Sulloway faults the editors of the Fliess correspondence for failing to
recognize that Fliess “was a pioneer in the field of infantile sexuality”
(Sulloway, 1991, p. 250). However, just as Fliess’s contributions to
bisexuality and infant sexuality should not be obscured by attributing his
views to Freud, so too should Fliess not be portrayed as scooping what had
already been thematic in Victorian pediatric medicine. To correct the record,
discussions of infantile sexuality were numerous, not sparse, before Freud and
Fliess. They began after the middle of the nineteenth century, although they
did not proliferate in the Continental literature until later on (Carter,
1983). The widespread pre-Fliessian belief that hysteria was sexual in nature
inspired investigations of sexuality in
hysterical children. Accordingly, clinical reports on infant sexuality—a
majority of which focused on masturbation—were authored by Behrend in 1860,
Jacobi in 1876, Fleischmann in 1878, Lindner in 1879, Smith in 1880, Scherpf in
1884, and Herz in 1885 (Carter, 1983). As for Freud’s objection in The Aetiology of Hysteria to the
argument that the infantile sexual episode cannot be the cause of hysteria
because such episodes were more common than its later clinical picture, he was
only responding to conjectures about the relationship between the two as
discussed in the pediatric literature of his day (Carter, 1983, p. 194). In an
eye-opening monograph, Kern (1973) details the way in which many of the alleged
Freudian discoveries, from infantile sexuality to psychosexual stages of
fixation and their impact on later character traits, made a prior debut in the
nineteenth century pediatric literature. Such studies were conducted shortly
after the midpoint of the century. The conviction that it was Freud alone who
originated this intellectual tradition is undoubtedly due to the promotional
efforts of psychoanalysts to advertise the revolutionary nature of his
discoveries. More often than not, this was at the expense of ignoring the more
extensive literature that preceded him. As a case in point, we find Freud in
his 1905 Three Essays declaring the
uniqueness of his contribution to the understanding of sexuality in children:
“So far as I know, not a single author has clearly recognized the regular
existence of a sexual instinct in childhood” (Kern, 1973, p. 118). This
pronouncement is astonishing in light of the depth of understanding about the
subject detailed in the pre-Freudian work of Maudsley in 1867, Perez in 1886,
Groos in 1899, Bell in 1902, Ellis in 1903, Sollier in 1891, Barnes in 1892,
Dessoir in 1894, Dallemagne in 1894, and probably numerous others.
(8) It was Cioffi (1988) who first questioned whether all
sexual games—like doctor and nurse games—initiated by children should be
characterized as abusive. Were
enemas, decades ago thought to be a home remedy for assorted gastrointestinal
ailments, sexually abusive when administered to children on a more frequent
basis than nowadays considered medically advisable? Lastly, is sexual
abusiveness toward children definitionally linked to the legal notion of mens rea in the mind of the perpetrator?
In other words, can adults sexually abuse children if the episode in question
is accidental or non-purposeful? Under the looser Freudian definition of
“trauma” in the originary period, accidental frottage during the sexually
precocious phase might have met criteria for a pathogenic event, although
perpetrator intentionality would have been lacking. Are enemas abusive if the parent
mistakenly believes irrigation of the bowels on a regular basis is feasible as
a health measure? Perhaps it is necessary to distinguish between what is traumatic and what is abusive.
(9) It was not only the foreboding aspect of the
landscape at the foothills of the Carpathians, nor the sinister demeanor of
Count Dracula that caught Jonathan Harker’s attention in his travels to Eastern
Europe. As if to set the stage for the terrifying drama that was to unfold,
Harker’s racially tinged remarks about the peasants and villagers he met along
the way to Castle Dracula are also noteworthy. He finds them fearful,
superstitious, strange-looking, and sickly despite their gay attire. Their food
is good, although it makes him “thirsty.” The women are pretty, except when you
draw close to find “how clumsy they are about the waist.” The Slovaks are the
most “barbaric”: while “picturesque,” they are not “prepossessing,” and on
stage they would be mistaken for an “Oriental band of brigands.” They are, he
reassures himself, quite harmless and “rather wanting in self-assertion.”
Harker’s reaction to Eastern Europeans is the initial nicety or expression of
wonderment, followed by the patronizing remark. He is quintessentially the
western European, oblivious to his sense of racial superiority. On the other
hand, Count Dracula’s litany of virtues about his own “race,” harkening back to
Attila the Hun, betrays his conviction that his lineage is moribund. Indeed,
the literal and lineal notions of “blood” shift imperceptibly back and forth at
the beginning of the novel—authored in the auspicious year of 1897!
REFERENCES
American Psychiatric Association
(1994). Diagnostic and statistical manual
of mental disorders, fourth edition. Washington, D.C.: American Psychiatric Association.
Austin, J. L. (1960). Sense and Sensibilia. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ayllon, T., and Haughton, E. (1964).
Modification of symptomatic verbal behavior of mental patients. Behavior Research and Therapy, 2, 87-97.
Ayllon, T., and Haughton, E. and
Hughes, H. (1965). Interpretation of symptoms. Fact or fiction? Behavior
Research and Therapy, 3, 1-7.
Balmary, M. (1979). L’Homme Aux Statues: Freud et la Faute
Cachee du Pere. Paris.
Baroja, J. C. (1965). The World of the Witches. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Bowlby,
R. (2004). Introduction to Studies in
Hysteria. London: Penguin Books.
Breuer, J. and Freud, S. (1895). Studies in hysteria. SE, 2.
Carter, K. C. (1983). Infantile
hysteria and infantile sexuality in late nineteenth-century German-language
literature. Medical History, 27, 186-196.
Cioffi, F. (1972). Wolheim on Freud. Inquiry. 15, 171-186.
Cioffi, F. (1974). Was Freud a liar? Listener, 91, 172-174.
Cioffi, F. (1988). “Exegital
myth-making” in Grünbaum’s indictment of Popper and exoneration of Freud. In P.
Clark and C. Wright (Eds.), Mind,
Psychoanalysis, and Science. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 61-87.
Cohen, L., Berzoff, J. and Elin M.
(1995). Dissociative Identity Disorder. Northdale,
New Jersey: Jason Aronson, Inc.
Crews, F. (1986). Skeptical Engagements. New York: Oxford University Press.
Crews, F. (1995). The Memory Wars: Freud’s Legacy in Dispute. New York: New York
Review of Books.
Crews, F. (Ed.) (1998). Unauthorized Freud: Doubters Confront a
Legend. New York: Viking.
Ebersole, P. and Ebersole, S.
(1993). The Abuse of Innocence: The McMartin Preschool Trial. Buffalo, New York: Prometheus Press.
Ellenberger, H.F. (1970). The
Discovery of the Unconscious. New York Basic Books.
Erdelyi, M. (1984). The recovery of
unconscious (inaccessible) memories: Laboratory studies of hypermnesia. In G.
Bower (Ed.), The Psychology of Learning
and Motivation: Advances in Research and Theory, Vol. 18, New York:
Academic Press, pp. 95-127.
Erwin, E. (1993). Philosophers on
Freudianism. In J. Earman, et. Al., Philosophical problems of the internal and
external worlds. Essays on the
philosophy of Adolph Grünbaum. Pittsburgh
and Konstanz: University of Pittsburgh Press and Univestätsverlag, pp. 409-460.
Esterson, A. (1993). Seductive Mirage: An Exploration of the Work
of Sigmund Freud. Chicago,
Illinois: Open Court.
Farrell, J. (1996). Freud’s paranoid quest: Psychoanalysis and
modern suspicion. New York: New York University Press.
Féré, C. S. (1884). La famille névropathique: Theorie
teratologique de l’hérédité et la dégénerescence, Archives de Neurologic, 7, 1-43.
Fish, S. (1986). Withholding the
missing portion. Power, meaning and persuasion in Freud’s “The Wolf Man” Times Literary Supplement. August 29,
935-938.
Fishberg, M. (1911). The
Jews: A Study of Race and Environment. New York: W. Scott.
Freud, S. The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund
Freud. 24 volumes. James Strachey
(Ed.) London: Hogarth Press and the Institute of Psycho-Analysis (1953-1974).
(Hereafter referred to as SE).
Freud, S. (1988). Hysteria. SE, 1, 41-57.
Freud, S. (1896a). Heredity and the
aetiology of the neuroses. SE, 3,
143-146.
Freud, S. (1896b). Further remarks on
the neuro-psychoses of defence. SE, 3,
162-185.
Freud, S. (1896c). The aetiology of hystera. SE, 3, 191-221.
Freud, S. (1905). Three essays on the
theory of sexuality. SE, 7, 123-243.
Freud, S. (1912-1913). Totem and taboo. SE, 13, 1-161.
Freud, S. (1918). From the history of an
infantile neurosis. SE, 17, 7-123.
Freud, S. (1925). An autobiographical
study. SE, 20, 7-74.
Freud, S. (1931). Female sexuality. SE, 21, 221-243.
Freud, S. (1964). The Letters of Sigmund Freud. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Freud, S. (1886a). Report on Freud’s
studies in Paris and Berlin. SE, 1.
Freud, S. (1886b). Preface to the translation of Charcot’s
lectures on the diseases of the nervous system. SE, 1.
Freud, S. (1893). Charcot, SE, 3.
Gay, P. (1988). Freud: A Life For Our Time. New York: Doubleday.
Gilman, S. (1993a). Freud, Race, and Gender. Princeton, New
Jersey: Princeton University.
Gilman, S. (1993b). The Case of Sigmund Freud: Medicine and
Identity at the Fin de Siecle. Baltimore, Maryland: The John Hopkins
University Press.
Glicklhorn, J. and Glicklhorn, R.
(1960). Sigmund Freuds academische
Laufbahn im Lichte der Dokumente. Vienna and Innsbruck: Urban &
Schwartzenberg.
Gould, S. J. (1981). The Mismeasure of Man. New York: W. W.
Norton.
Grünbaum, A. (1979). Is Freudian
psychoanalytic theory pseudo-scientific by Karl Popper’s criterion of
demarcation? American Philosophical Quarterly, 16, 131-141.
Grünbaum, A. (1984). The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A
Philosophical Critique.
Berkeley, California: University of
California Press.
Grunbaum, A. (1991). Etiology and
therapy in psychoanalytic theory. Behavioral
and Brain Sciences, 14, No. 4., December, 729-732.
Hacking, I. (1995). Rewriting the Soul: Multiple Personality and
the Sciences of Memory. Princeton,
New Jersey: Princeton University Press.
Henningsen, G. (1969). The papers of
Alonso de Salazar Frías: A Spanish witchcraft polemic 1610-14. Temenos. Studies in comparative religion
presented by scholars in Denmark, Finland, Norway, and Sweden, 5, 85-106.
Henningsen, G. (1980). The Witches’ Advocate: Basque Witchcraft and
the Spanish Inquisition. Reno, Nevada: University of Nevada Press.
Israels, H. and Schatzman, M.
(1993). The seduction theory. History of Psychiatry. 4, 23-59.
Kern, S. (1973). Freud and the
discovery of child sexuality. History of
Childhood Quarterly, 1, 117-141.
Krasner, L. (1958). A technique for
investigating the relationship between the behavior cues of the examiner and
the verbal behavior of the patient. Journal of Consulting Psychology, 22, 364-366.
Krull, M. (1986). Freud and His Father. New York: Norton.
Levin, K. (1944). Freud’s Early Psychology of the Neuroses: A Historical Perspective,
Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Lynn, S. and Rhue, J. W. (1994). Dissociation. New York: Guilford Press.
Macmillan M. (1991). Freud Evaluated: The Completed Arc, New
York: North-Holland.
Masson, J. M. (1984). The Assault on Truth: Freud’s Suppression of
the Seduction Theory, New York: Farrar, Straus, and Girox.
Masson, J. M. (1985). The Complete Letters of Sigmund Freud to
Wilhelm Fliess: 1887-1904, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University
Press.
McGrath, W. J. (1986). Freud’s Discovery of Psychoanalysis: The
Politics of Hysteria. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press.
Monter, E. W. (1969). European Witchcraft, New York: John
Wiley.
Murray, C. and Herrnstein, R. J.
(1994). The Bell Curve. New York: The
Free Press.
Sachs, D. (1989). In fairness to Freud:
A critical notice of The foundations of
psychoanalysis by Adolph Grünbaum. The
Philosophical Review, vol. XCVIII, No. 3, July, 349-378.
Salzinger, K. and Pisoni, S.
(1958). Reinforcement of affect
responses of schizophrenics during the clinical interview. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 57, 84-90.
Schatzman, M. (1992). Freud: Who
seduced whom? New Scientist, 21, March, 35-37.
Schimek, J. G. (1987). Fact and fantasy
in the seduction theory: A historical review. Journal of the American Psychoanalytical Association, 35, 937-965.
Sebald, H. (1995). Witch-Children: From Salem Witch-Hunts to Modern Courtrooms. Amherst,
New York: Prometheus Books.
Smith, M. and Pazder, L. (1980). Michelle Remembers. New York: Congdon
and Lattes.
Stewart, L. (1976). Freud before
Oedipus: Race and heredity in the origins of psychoanalysis. Journal of the History of Biology, 9, 215-228.
Stratford, L. (1988). Satan’s Underground. Eugene, Oregon:
Harvest House.
Sulloway, F. (1991). Reassessing
Freud’s case histories: The social construction of psychoanalysis Isis 82, 245-275.
Sulloway, F. (1992). Freud: Biologist of the Mind. Cambridge,
Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
Szasz, T. S. (1961). The Myth of Mental Illness: Foundations of a
Theory of Personal Conduct, New York: Harper & Row.
Thornton, E. M. (1983). The Freudian Fallacy: An Alternative View of
Freudian Theory. Garden City, New Jersey.
Vetter, I. (1988). Die Kontroverse um Sigmund Freuds sogennante Verfuhrungtheorie. MA
thesis Bayern: Catholic University Eichstatt.
Weber, E. (1986). France, Fin de Siècle. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Belknap Press of
Harvard University Press.
Webster, R.
(1996). Why Freud Was Wrong: Sin, Science
and Psychoanalysis. New York:
Harper Collins.
Wilcocks, R. (1994). Maelzel’s Chess Player: Sigmund Freud and
the Rhetoric of Deceit. Lanham, Maryland:
Rowman & Littlefield.
Young-Bruehl, E. (1995). A history of
Freud biographies. In Micale, M. S. and
Porter R. (Eds.), Discovering the History
of Psychiatry, (pp. 157-173). New York: Oxford University Press.
Film Review: “A
Dangerous Method”: Blowing the Cover on the Shrinks
David Begelman
You’re
tempted to think that the producers of the 2011 film, “A Dangerous Method” were
ignoring much of the commentary on psychoanalysis down through the years.
There’s a spin to this film that betokens a backdoor reediting of history by those
intent on gilding the lily.
The movie is in part inspired by psychologist
John Kerr’s definitive account of the early association of Sigmund Freud and Carl
Gustav Jung entitled, “A Most Dangerous Method.” Despite his eye-opening
recapitulation of the relationship between the two celebrated figures, Canadian
director David Cronenberg’s film paints a lopsided contest between an ingenuous
Jung (Michael Fassbender), his sexual attraction to a patient, Sabina Spielrein
(Keira Knightley), and a supremely avuncular Freud (Viggo Mortensen).
While
the film reenacts some actual events in the relationship between the two
psychiatrists, it omits a good deal of the nitty-gritty of their saga, as
though they were always flying high on the wings of sagacity and integrity. Real
history turns in a different verdict than Cronenberg’s manicured version of
things.
Jung,
a darling of the New Age set, was given to other dalliances outside of his marriage
to his wife Emma (played by Sarah Gadon in the film), including one with Toni
Wolff—when he wasn’t battling psychotic episodes, or giving vent to anti-Semitic
palaver as an enthusiast for the superiority of the “Aryan unconscious” over
the Jewish version of same.
And
Freud was hardly one to point the finger at Jung’s sexual improprieties, as
Cronenberg’s film portrays. He had a thing for his sister-in-law, Minna
Bernays, who lived with him and his family for long stretches. The smoking gun
in his affair with her was an entry in a hotel registry when the pair were on
holiday together in the Swiss Alps. (His wife Martha was at that time at home,
tending to the children.) Before contemporary scholars like Peter Swales got
the goods on him, allegations of Freud’s infidelity were dismissed by his
followers as a Jungian smear campaign.
Contrary
to what is implied in the film, Freud’s supposed record of “cure” was dismal
rather than stellar, while his disciples slavishly attempted to curry favor
with him as though he was, as one critic has averred, “a petty generalissimo,”
rather than a scientist.
There’s
little in “A Dangerous Method” that rises above a sugar-coated view of the
early Freud-Jung relationship. It’s also largely a transparent attempt to mystify
the Jung-Spielrein affair with highfalutin “insights” over a liaison that
boiled down to an escapade between an ambitious woman of sadomasochistic bent
and her randy psychoanalyst. While Jung is depicted in “A Dangerous Method” as experiencing
remorse over the professional boundary-violation, his encounter with Sabina was
probably the same kind thing it is for most husbands with a wandering eye, international
reputations notwithstanding. Except he called his fling “poetry,” a euphemism
to die for, since in his case “the talking cure” involved more than talking or
poetry.
Fassbender
as Jung puts his best foot forward in a script that is, alas, pretty thin
material from a narrative standpoint. Mortensen, one of the most capable
Hollywood actors if his performances in “Eastern Promises” (2007), and “History
of Violence” (2008)—both also directed by Cronenberg—are any indication, was a
polished and insinuating Freud. Keira
Knightly’s characterization as Sabina was on the overdrawn, spastic side, even
given her diagnosis as “hysteric.” The classification, ever popular in
Victorian theorizing, is currently an obsolete one, saturated as it is with
ambiguity and culture-bound intrusions that make it virtually worthless as a psychiatric
category.
“A
Dangerous Method” is now available on DVD, having had a mercifully short run in
neighborhood movie theaters.
Does Shakespeare Need Freud?
D. A. Begelman
I’d
like to speak today about the psychoanalytic spin on Shakespeare. Some of you
may be familiar with this kind of glossing of his plays. There are, to be sure,
countless examples of the approach, although for present purposes let’s focus
on one, perhaps the most notable of the genre. It was authored by Dr. Ernest
Jones, Freud’s biographer, who was also a member of his six-person secret
“Committee.” Formed in 1912, it comprised a group of close associates charged
with maintaining the integrity of the psychoanalytic movement. The membership
feared revisionism from within by those like Jung, Adler, Stekel, and others
perceived as deviating from a party line.
Jones’s
1949 monograph (originally published in the January 1910 issue of The American Journal of Psychology) was
entitled, Hamlet and Oedipus: A Classic
Study in the Psychoanalysis of Literature. (1) It intended to show why the melancholy prince delayed avenging his
dead father, a sovereign by the same name, Hamlet. The intellectual hero of
Shakespeare’s tragedy learns that his uncle Claudius murdered his own brother,
the former king. Hamlet takes upon himself the task of avenging his father’s
death by resolving to dispatch Claudius with the encouragement (if not
occasional hectoring) of his father’s seeming ghost. I say “seeming” because in
one famous soliloquy Hamlet registers doubts about whether the ghost was real
or the Devil in disguise.
In
order to erase his lingering doubt—and one that comports well with the early
modern belief in the shape-shifting powers of the Devil—Hamlet contrives to
stage a play, a doctored version of The
Murder of Gonzago. The drama portrays the poisoning of a monarch by his
brother, and Claudius’s agitated reaction to its enactment convinces Hamlet it
betrays his uncle’s guilt. Yet Hamlet does not kill his uncle until the end of
the play. Jones’s interpretation of this “procrastination” is a boilerplate
spin on the drama, and one shared by Freud himself: Hamlet’s Oedipus Complex.
The complex, according to Freud, involves a repressed wish to kill the father
in order to sexually possess the mother. According to Jones, killing Claudius
so resonates with Hamlet’s unconscious Oedipal wish, murdering his uncle would
bring the wish too close to the surface of consciousness. Jones felt that
Hamlet’s delay could be thus understood in the light of this inner conflict.
I
have always been troubled about this formulation, although to be fair to
psychoanalysts, reliance on the Oedipus Complex among their ranks has declined
sharply in recent years (2). On the way to downsizing this formative concept of
their theory, psychoanalysts came to distinguish between the “Oedipus Complex”
and the “Oedipal phase,” a distinction some might construe to be a bit on the
precious side.
What
human patterns reveal or otherwise confirm an Oedipus Complex? In other words,
what is its purported data-base, or those observations that make the complex a
reasonable theoretical conjecture? This turns out to be a challenge weightier
than we might imagine. For if the complex is an unconscious one, how do we get from ordinary patterns of
behavior—normal or abnormal—to what may strike us at first blush as a
counterintuitive, if not outlandish, scenario supposedly behind them? Those who
say that they never had incestuous thoughts about their mothers or fears of
castration by their fathers are reminded by psychoanalysts that such wishes are
not consciously entertained ideas. But the nagging question still remains: why
choose that unconscious scenario,
rather than some other we might select from numberless possibilities?
It
also may strike us as implausible that the evidence for the theory comes from
observations of patients in the consulting room. If the complex is unconscious,
neither do practitioners observe it in the raw. What they observe are ongoing
patterns of behavior we would never ordinarily attribute to anything like an
Oedipally-saturated scenario—never, that is, until a view of things becomes
colored by professionals in the thrall of such a notion. No one before Freud
thought of an Oedipus conflict. And that should come as something of a surprise
to us all. After all, if the complex is a compelling explanation of a
bewildering variety of behavioral patterns, what was keeping theorists from
cottoning onto it long before the end of the 19th century?
To
reemphasize the point, Freud originally posited the complex as a universal unconscious scenario: everyone
harbors it. He deemed it to be such an ingredient aspect of human development
that personality as we know it would be impossible without it. Accordingly, we
would be hard pressed to come up with a specimen of ongoing behavior exempt
from its effects. Presumably then, there are no naturally occurring personality
styles or actions without the inevitable stamp of the complex, despite the
enormous range of personality patterns that exist. If that is true, it seems
paradoxical to characterize a particular pattern like that of Hamlet as
evidence of the complex when there are no counterexamples against which it can
be meaningfully contrasted (3).
Let’s
highlight this point by an analogy. If, during the course of a regular medical
examination, your physician declares that you show signs of mental illness, you
would be understandably perplexed by such a diagnosis if the doctor insisted
that any possible way you behaved was a sign of, or consistent with, having the
condition. You’d certainly be within your rights to wonder what he could
possibly mean by “mental illness” if any conceivable pattern that you present
to him was a presumptive symptom of the condition.
Suppose
someone authored a play very much unlike Shakespeare’s, in which our hero, so
dismayed by the two months interval between his father’s death and the
remarriage of his mother to his uncle Claudius, impulsively kills the latter
before the end of the first act. Literary scholars might protest we don’t have
much of a play at that point, and they’re probably right. But what would a
psychoanalyst say in the grip of the Freud/Jones idea of the complex in
question? Not that a swift and early murder contradicts the provisions of
psychoanalytic theory. He couldn’t say this, for the simple reason that as he
understands his formulation, all types of behavior either betray the stamp of
the repressed Oedipal wish, or else are consistent with having it. After all,
and in order to bring this newer scenario in line with the theory in question,
it is only necessary to assume that the murder of Claudius with dispatch
mirrors precisely the central theme of the Oedipus Complex, namely, killing the
paternal competitor for mother love. All that is needed for this alternative
scenario to represent a “deduction” from psychoanalytic theory (or at least an
action consistent with it) is to hold that murdering Claudius early on
discloses an Oedipal conflict in which thematic material for some reason does
not reach the level of consciousness so that the final act of regicide need not
be postponed!
On
the other hand, we might surmise that the unconscious material does invade consciousness, the
explanation for why Hamlet behaves the way he does before the end of our hack
drama, or, indeed, why any of his ongoing behavior has the features it exhibits
after the murder. Whatever they turn out to be, the hypothesized Oedipal drama
is confirmed. The conclusion is inescapable: Hamlet’s procrastination can
hardly be considered evidence of an Oedipal problem when there is no way he
could have possibly behaved in relation to Claudius that could not likewise be
attributed to it, given the configuration of mother, father, sex, and murder as
ingredients of a dramatic scenario. He delays killing Claudius because of an
Oedipal conflict, but if he summarily kills him, it’s still the Oedipal thing
in operation—only with a different upshot.
To
summarize: we have reason to question why Shakespeare’s Hamlet procrastinates
out of Oedipal motives if precisely the same motives explain why he wouldn’t
procrastinate at all in a revised—and considerably inferior—play. Ernest Jones,
it appears, seemed oblivious to the fact that if the Oedipus Complex explains
everything, it really explains nothing, since its grid fits all behaviors, all
traits, all styles, all comers, with—as they say in my trade—no
contraindications.
Dr.
Jones’s treatise seems to contain other telltale signs of fudging. If he
believed that Hamlet’s delay in discharging his filial obligation to kill his
uncle was prompted by unconscious Oedipal fantasies, what then do we make of
his slaying Polonius behind the arras in Queen Gertrude’s bedchamber? I quote
the melancholy prince:
How now! a rat?
Dead! for a ducat, dead!
Thou wretched, rash, intruding fool,
farewell!...
I took thee for thy better!
“I
took thee for thy better” (Italics
mine). Whom did Hamlet think he was killing in Act III, scene IV, if not
Claudius—as another psychoanalyst, Dr. Theodore Lidz, acknowledges in his book,
Hamlet’s Enemy: Madness and Myth in
Hamlet? (4)
Ernest
Jones, sensing that the killing of Polonius contradicts his formulation about
Hamlet’s continuing delay in killing Claudius—if that is whom he thought he was
stabbing through the curtain—had this to say in a footnote: “I find Loening’s
detailed argument quite conclusive that Hamlet did not have the king in mind when
he struck this blow” (1949, p. 37). Jones’s argument here is strained, and
obviously in the service of seeing Hamlet consistently
delay finishing off his uncle. Yet, and in line with what we have been
saying, why Jones feels there is some inconsistency between having an Oedipal
conflict and killing someone Hamlet identified with his father remains obscure.
If no behavior we might imagine refutes having the complex, then certainly
killing a father substitute before the end of Act I doesn’t refute it either.
Maybe in light of this, Jones should have revisited his assumption that Hamlet
didn’t think Polonius was Claudius.
The
Jones/Lidz discrepancy is intriguing from another standpoint. Two eminent
psychoanalysts derive inconsistent views about Hamlet’s mind-set from the same
construct, and moreover, consider them straightforward deductions from theory!
Since there are no specific features of behavior that uniquely represent
consequences of harboring an Oedipus Complex or, alternatively, represent
evidence against having it, the incongruity is not that all surprising. Indeed,
Lidz’s opinion that Hamlet thought he was killing Claudius when he was
dispatching Polonius was for this psychoanalyst not contrary to the
Oedipally-saturated spin on Shakespeare’s hero. Accordingly, if the commentary by both psychoanalysts is a model
of psychoanalytic inference in general, the system is less a scientific theory
than it is a sieve through which any potential observation can be filtered.
Going
on to reinforce his point that Hamlet did not think he was killing Claudius,
Jones declares: “After all, he had just left the king engrossed in prayer, and
the latter could hardly have rushed in front of him to [Gertrude’s] bedroom”
(1949, p.37). Jones’s remarks are careless; there are no Shakespearean clues
concerning Castle Elsinore time schedules for separate characters. Claudius
rises and exits from praying at the close of Act III, scene III, while scene IV
of the same act opens in the queen’s bedroom without any indication of the time
elapsing between Hamlet’s taking leave of the King in prayer, and the imagined
entrances of him and Claudius into the queen’s chamber. Consequently, the
assumption that Hamlet could not have
believed that Claudius was hiding in Gertrude’s bedchamber—and who else might
it have been in such a compromising situation?—is gratuitous.
At
the end of the play, Hamlet does assassinate Claudius, an act that on the face
of it in conflict with Jones’s theory of Oedipally-derived dilatory action. His
explanation of this is instructive about how psychoanalytic theorizing always
comes up smiling: “Only when [Hamlet] has made the final sacrifice and brought
himself to the door of death is he free to fulfil his duty, to avenge his
father, and to slay his other self—his uncle…The second [moment] is when he
actually kills the King, when the Queen is already dead and lost to him for
ever, so that his conscience is free of an ulterior motive for the murder”
(1949, p. 100).
Another
bit of fudging? Jones feels it’s a theoretical given that Oedipal fantasies do
not survive the actual death of the mother figure to maintain their hold on
whatever ongoing action is taken to spring from them. From whence does this
assumption derive? In another hypothetical drama, what if Hamlet, after
dispatching Laertes in the duel and coming to realize he is also poisoned,
still could not bring himself to kill Claudius, as he intended? What would a
psychoanalyst say here? That the same unconscious conflict still prevents our hero from slaying his uncle due to its hold upon
him? If so, the actual death of Gertrude means little one way or the other in
confirming the existence of a certain mental conflict during the course of
final events in the play. Yet it is used by Jones to salvage an otherwise arbitrary
formulation about why Hamlet is able to commit an act he was supposedly
resistant to committing for five Acts.
In
addition, if Gertrude’s death by poison frees Hamlet from delaying killing
Claudius as Jones insists, why shouldn’t the death of his own father, the
former king of Denmark, likewise free him from the unconscious need to
temporize for five acts? The murdered king from the outset of the drama is no
longer a paternal figure who is either alive or who because of this can
retaliate with a castration threat on the son who harbors incestuous feelings
for the mother figure. Should the objection to this be that the father figure
is nonetheless haunting Hamlet’s imagination as the ghost of a living presence,
we are moved to ask where in psychoanalytic theory is it specified that a ghost
is the functional equivalent of a living father in the Oedipal drama? Even if
Freud were right about the existence of an Oedipus Complex, his and Jones’s
spin on Hamlet’s alleged procrastination strains to ensure foregone
conclusions, arbitrary even from the standpoint of their own formulation!
It
may come as no surprise to you that when it comes to psychoanalytic
interpretations of literature, I happen to be a contrarian with a capital “C.”
I don’t see this as especially unique, since I am not alone. Whistleblowers on
Freud have been accumulating steadily in recent decades, and their critiques
are instructive. If nothing else, they force us to review time-honored ideas
more critically—whatever final judgment on them is turned in by history.
Long
after Freudolatry is relegated to the dustbin of scientific history—as in my
opinion I think it inevitably will be—remnants of its cultural impact will
survive to infiltrate ordinary language. We’ll still continue to characterize
the relationship between dependent children and their mothers as “Oedipal,” and
we’ll still call persons who are compulsive or stingy “anal.” But such idioms
will represent, even as they do much of the time these days, little more than
an exchange of one group of synonyms for another: “Anal” thus becomes merely an
adjective for “stingy” or “compulsive” on the linguistic exchange. And I dare
say that many of us who characterize others as “anal” haven’t the foggiest
notion about the original provenance of the term within classical
psychoanalytic theory. Allow me now an extended sidebar on Freud.
There
are countless books, journal articles, and other literary excursions into how
psychoanalytic theory illuminates great literature, its contributions to the
Shakespearean canon being only a case in point. Then there is an enormous
clinical literature devoted to the psychoanalytic approach to the treatment of
psychological disorders.
Those
of us who feel that Freud has little to contribute to understanding
Shakespeare—or, indeed, any other literary master—believe that his is a flawed
psychology. Our skepticism springs from theoretical concerns shared by a
widening constituency of critics whose ranks in the humanities and the social
sciences have been burgeoning steadily in recent years. Because of this, it’s a
mistake to assume that recent criticism of Freud’s system or its present day
incarnations represents nothing more than the murmurings of a disgruntled and
uncomprehending few, an insubstantial minority of backbiters. Quite the
opposite is true.
The
newer criticicism concedes that psychoanalytic theory in its older, orthodox
form or in any of its later evolutionary guises has been of historical
importance. With its acknowledged influence on modern thought, we cannot
reasonably view it as otherwise. By the same token, Ptolemy’s geocentric theory
of the universe was important, as were the demythologized cosmologies of
Anaximander, Xenophanes and Pythagoras, theories of trait transmission
formulated by Lamarck and Lysenko; systems of astrology, homeopathy, magic,
sorcery and witchcraft, and more recently, New Age folderol about indigo
children and Creation Science and Intelligent Design as so-called
“alternatives” to Darwin’s evolutionary theory. These schemes have been
unquestionably important because they have all been influential, although
skeptics among us might intimate, as did one philosopher, that importance is
not important—truth is (5).
Of
course, truth in some circles these days seems to be less of a popular
commodity, given industrious attempts to deconstruct it in some quarters of the
humanities. In the turgid prose of the poststructuralists, the quest for
objective “truth” is foolhardy, a chimera. Many of them have it that the proper
focus should be something called the “text,” a foundational cornerstone of
their new religion. And if you have the temerity to ask why one textual
interpretation is better than any other, poststructuralists—congregating
principally in literature departments of the academy—might inform you your
question is symptomatic of the “positivism” of a scientific age. For them, it’s
not that the truth is hard to uncover; it’s not even out there to be unearthed,
diligently or otherwise.
Likewise,
asking why one psychoanalytic interpretation of a dream is better than any
other might get you sized up as a troublemaker whose ulterior motive is an
unconscious wish to kill the father—Freud being the father figure in question.
Yet dwelling on the unconscious motivation for why a question is posed only
sidetracks obtaining an answer to it. More than this, it steeps discourse in a
ploy not uncommon among psychoanalysts: the genetic fallacy, or confusing the
truth-value of an answer with the motivation for raising a question. My reasons
for asking something may well be perverse, but this tells us nothing about the
truth or falsity of any answer supplied.
We
can summarize the groundswell of recent criticism of the house that Freud built
by enumerating several of its salient points:
---------Freud’s
psychoanalytic theory, far from blazing a trail of insights into our mental
apparatus, has a hard time getting corroborated by experimental psychology,
contrary to the commentary of humanities scholars, playwrights, philosophers,
novelists, movie directors like Alfred Hitchcock, and consulting room gurus.
For what it’s worth, experimental science is the only crucible capable of
testing the mettle of a behavioral science theory. Moreover, while
psychoanalysis has left its mark on scholars in a wide range of disciplines, it
has for decades been pretty much a joke in the austere corridors of
experimental psychology.
---------Such
cornerstones of psychoanalytic method as dream interpretation and free
association have no probative value in any established scientific crucible, nor
do psychoanalysts provide any rigorous basis for why they should. The route to
pathogens, or the psychic causes of “neurosis” (a currently defunct term in
psychiatric nomenclature) through free
association can be likened to an exploratory voyage of note across the
Atlantic. Columbus might manage to cross it with his navigational skills to be
sure, but why should he have assumed that where he landed was India? Had he
landed in India, what made him believe he would find there the gold to enrich
Spain’s economy? Or if he found it, that there was a sufficient supply to mine?
Or, if a sufficient supply, not tucked away in inaccessible hills?
---------The
root assumption that our dream life abounds in images that have symbolic value
or are drenched in wish-fulfillment is a leap of faith with little empirical
grounding. The method of free association, devised as it was to root out the
causal origins of neurosis, has been advertised by psychoanalysts as one royal
road to the unconscious, while the documented effects of such factors as
situational variables and suggestibility have been blithely ignored in the rush
to sanctify the technique. Even absenting the role of suggestion or derailment
from a proper mental spoor, what guarantees that the factor unearthed by free
association is actually a pathogen at all?
---------Despite
the promotional campaigns of its propagandists, there is currently no research
evidence to support the claim that psychoanalysis is any more effective than
any other therapeutic approach, while its track record on such disabilities as
panic disorder, obsessive-compulsive
disorder, substance abuse disorders, and certain sexual disorders, is dismal.
Psychoanalysts themselves have long acknowledged that disorders like schizophrenia,
bipolar disorder, or the autism spectrum disorders are beyond the reach of
their methods. Freud himself conceded this early in his career.
When
it comes to treatment in general, psychoanalytic practitioners often turn in a
less than stellar performance. Decades ago, the prestigious New York
Psychoanalytic Institute undertook a comparative study of the effectiveness of
psychoanalytic treatment on patients for whom its practices were considered
appropriate—a rather selective group of troubled persons, anyhow. The results
were so disappointing, they were summarily suppressed by the bigwigs at the
Institute.
As
far as Freud’s original caseload goes, so-called “cures,” are either
non-existent, as in the cases of the “hysteric” Dora (Ida Bauer) and the Wolf
Man (Sergei Pankejeff), are misrepresented as delivering up disclosures of
sexual abuse that turn out to be scenarios Freud himself may have foisted upon
his female patients—as in the pioneering days of his 1896 Seduction Theory, or
else are concocted tales pasted together from the facts of his own life, not
those of actual patients he was treating.
In
the case of the Ratman (Ernst Lanzer), one for which Freud famously claimed a
cure, and for this reason showcased it in his 1908 address to the First
International Psychoanalytic Congress, incongruities between his progress notes
and his final presentation, not to mention its implausible reconstructions,
stare one in the face. The failure of serious follow-up after three months of
treatment make Freud’s prognostications about successful outcome dubious in the
extreme. The case of “Little Hans,” supposedly a pioneering study of childhood
phobia, is a stunning example of how a patient’s disclosures can be twisted to
fit preordained theoretical biases. And the patient in question, Herbert Graf,
was treated by his father under the sway of a long-distance Freud!
---------Psychoanalytic
theory has been notoriously resistant to an essential feature of scientific
formulations worthy of the mantle, namely, falsifiability. As we have seen in
the case of Hamlet, its practitioners are hard put to specify unambiguously the
specific behavioral data or patterns that would decisively falsify its central
concepts. The theory functions more like a conceptual funnel through which any
fact produces confirmation of a master template. The psychoanalyst’s view of
the world can be likened to a passing parade in conceptual lock-step, as if in
the face of any clinical disorder the incessant rallying cry is: “We know the
drill.” Creaking attempts to specify hypothetically falsifying data for central
concepts may from time to time surface (as in Freud’s attempt to give them lip
service in his 1937 essay, “Constructions in Analysis”), but they ring hollow
when one considers the assumptive flavor of overriding notions in ongoing
psychoanalytic practice. It is one thing to broadcast the possibility of falsification, and quite another to operate as if
such public reassurances were little more than empty promises. Routinely,
everyone has an Oedipus complex, or a stockpile of repressions, and there is no
conceivable observation that would refute this.
---------Psychoanalytic
theory foists a view of explanation with what I would call an imperial
outreach. It amounts to casting the net of a strictly motivational psychology
over behavior, and quite prematurely, given the state of our present knowledge.
It is not at all apparent that aberrant behavior is always driven by invisible
motives, and it is premature to insist that there are always underlying
unconscious reasons, rather than
simply causes, for certain patterns.
---------The
central concept of psychoanalytic theory, that of repression, has received
increased critical scrutiny in recent years, possibly because of its central
role in such acrimonious debates as the one over recovered memories of early
sexual abuse. It should be noted that the debate runs a gamut of opinion from
researchers who find no support for a concept of repression in over sixty years
of laboratory studies, to clinicians who are convinced of its operation as an
incontrovertible truth. The latter find experimental studies to be wanting for
the reason that they are viewed as artificially contrived laboratory exercises
lacking the dynamic aspect of real life drama. The posture is ironic for
historical reasons. When earlier laboratory studies seemed to suggest a basis
for the notion of repression, psychoanalysts were eager to reference this as
the scientific backup for a cherished concept. When later, more rigorous studies
cast doubt on the virtual existence of repression, the same constituency
pooh-poohed the findings as irrelevant to real life problems (6). Freud himself
did not harbor such contradictory sentiments. He was dismissive of all
laboratory research on psychoanalytic concepts, whether confirmatory or
discouraging, from the outset. In 1934, five years before his death, he said as
much to a psychologist, Saul Rosenzweig, who felt he had data that confirmed
Freud’s concept of repression.
--------In the
face of the disconcerting results of outcome studies, fresh spin on
psychoanalytic theory has evolved. Gone is the older emphasis on therapeutic
effectiveness, to be replaced by a newer focus on the vagaries of so-called
transference and countertransference, as if such rarefied concerns have
anything to do with the reasons for which patients seek treatment. In my own
clinical career in the trenches, patients enter treatment in order to find
relief from such things as marital discord, mood disorder, anxiety, psychosis,
substance-abuse, obsessive-compulsive disorder, attention deficit hyperactivity
disorder, or aggression, etc. They do not usually come for esoteric or
speculative excursions into the realm of “self-understanding” brokered by
analysts. Nor is any such venture
necessary in order to resolve their personal difficulties.
--------Given
the time and cost a psychoanalytic course of treatment takes (or used to take),
it is premature to assume that psychological changes introduced during its
course can be attributed to it. The tendency to do so blithely ignores ongoing
effects that are introduced over time in untreated control groups, against
which any therapeutic effect must be measured. In addition, if therapeutic
success is to any extent measured by verbal reports of patients, the time,
expense, and commitment to treatment may well contribute to positive judgments
predicted by Cognitive Dissonance Theory (7). That is, verbal appraisals of
their own treatment by patients swing in the direction of their behavioral
commitment to psychotherapy, whatever its form or actual reality of
improvement. If you want an untarnished report about whether a parishioner has
been saved by God, make sure first he or she hasn’t spent a lifetime
proselytizing for the faith.
--------A number
of contemporary psychoanalysts, reeling from the fancied depredations of
biological psychiatry, the success of short-term treatment like
Cognitive-Behavioral Therapy, and the financial strait-jacket of insurance
industry policies, have maintained that psychoanalysis, unlike other nostrums,
is the last frontier of deeper self-understanding. The stance is gratuitous.
The alleged self-truths unearthed by any therapeutic method remain to be
evaluated by independent scientific criteria. It is far from apparent that a
treatment procedure based on such question-begging techniques as dream
interpretation, free association, or the exotic surmises yielded up by
so-called “transference” analyses has a proprietary claim to truths no other
method can achieve.
--------The
relationship of psychoanalytic theory to historiography is a topsy-turvy one.
History is reconstructed by the special methods of historians, not by
psychologists like Freud, indulging their versions of “psychohistory.” The
latter can at best only aspire to be a dilatory end game that spruces up
knowledge already established through the methodology of the other discipline.
To lose sight of the primacy of the historian in reconstructing the past
results in such extravagant conjectures as Freud’s insistence in his treatise Moses and Monotheism that Moses was an
Egyptian who was murdered by Jews who later sanctified him due to the guilt
they experienced over his death (8). This is a concocted yarn, just like the
theory propounded in Freud’s Totem and Taboo
that real life Oedipal dramas of murdering the father were actually enacted in
the infancy of our species, and their “repressed” memories passed on as a
genetic lineage. Such a formulation defies any current acceptable theory about
the way human traits are developed and inherited.
---------The
progressive whittling away of theories and assumptions that were once an
ingredient aspect of Freud’s psychoanalysis is as much a legacy of the system
as anything else (9). What survives are institutional vehicles equivocating
between the imagined virtues of analyzability and treatability. Accordingly,
when a track record on therapeutic efficacy is shown to be poor or lackluster,
damage control involves resorting to a default theoretical stance that insists
symptoms can still be effectively “analyzed”—as though the validity of the
interpretive scheme in question can be taken for granted.
----------That
psychoanalytic case studies have an appeal for the literary imagination goes
without saying. But so do the stories manufactured by the likes of Sir Arthur
Conan Doyle, Edgar Allen Poe, Georges Simenon, or, on a less somber note, Damon
Runyon or Raymond Chandler. The detour into psychoanalytic story-telling is not
without appeal. Part of the fascination of this type of theorizing is its
beguiling way of combining a purportedly scientific mission with an abundance
of quasi-literary narrative resembling detective-story sleuthing. As early as
1895, we find the father of psychoanalysis admitting that, “It still strikes me
as strange that the case histories I write should read like short stories and
that, as one might say, they lack the serious stamp of science.” Of course,
literary comparisons can be pushed too far. When it comes to prose style
itself, it’s a safe bet you’d never confuse a published psychoanalyst or his
poststructuralist incarnations like Jacques Lacan (10) with Ernest Hemingway!
----------We
need not harbor any illusions about the newer criticism convincing Freudolators
that there is something seriously amiss in psychoanalytic theory and
treatment—from its outset. Fostering skepticism about a system of thought that
has a tide of historical enthusiasm on its side is not an easy task. Similarly,
we need have no illusions about convincing believers in Intelligent Design that
the Bacterial Flagellum, the Blood Clotting Cascade, or the eye are not
“irreducibly complex,” or that fancied gaps in the fossil record are evidence
of absence when they are only absence of evidence (11). Similarly, it’s hard to
convince a bamboozled laity that psychoanalytic theory is without explanatory
virtue when its widespread popularity seems to suggest otherwise (12).
----------The
insularity of psychoanalytic practice, an in-house pattern acknowledged even by
its own membership (13), has more serious implications than imagined. Aside
from this aspect of practice in relation to outside investigators, what about
the knowledge the clan possesses about specific patterns of treatment within
the fold? It is conceivable that commonalities among the behaviors of
practitioners are artifacts of an illusory consistency generated by published
writings. How can we be certain that abstract theoretical ideas are fleshed out
in similar ways in the consulting room in the absence of institutional vehicles
that ensure transparency?
A
famous philosopher and contemporary of Freud felt the latter was less the
originator of a scientific psychology than the creator of a new mythology
wrapped in a novel vocabulary of metaphors about people (14). Freud, of course,
thought otherwise, and unlike current poststructuralists indulging the “text”
or the freewheeling extravagance called “hermeneutics,” believed his brainchild
was a true science of the mind, a psychology that laid bare the actual causal
determinants of our behavior. In my opinion, history will turn in a rather
different verdict.
There
is more—much more—to be said about the psychoanalytic approach to Shakespeare.
Iago’s supposed unconscious homosexuality in relation to Othello? Don’t get me
started. As for postmodern attempts to salvage the musty system, when the ocean
liner is sinking, you head for the lifeboats, not the scotch tape.
I
admit that my remarks have been on the extremely negative side. For those who
feel that they can be dismissed precisely for this reason, I have only these
words of my favorite Shakespearean hero: I
must be cruel, only to be kind; this bad begins and worse remains behind.
FOOTNOTES
(1) Jones, E. (1949). Hamlet
and Oedipus: A classic study in the psychoanalysis of literature. Garden
City: New York, Doubleday & Company, Inc.
(2) The shifting
character of the complex even during Freud’s career is documented in Simon, B.
and Blass, R. B., The development and vicissitudes of Freud’s ideas on the Oedipus
Complex. In Neu, J. (Ed.) 1991. The
Cambridge companion to Freud, New York: Cambridge University Press, pp.
161-174.
(3) The case of
children growing up in one-parent homes since birth would seem to represent a
decisive test of the theory in question. If such children for the most part
mature into normal personalities, this refutes the contention that “normalcy”
is an outgrowth of a successfully resolved Oedipus Complex. You can’t resolve a
conflict predicated upon a family configuration that is absent in the case of
one-parent households!
(4) Lidz T.
(1975) Hamlet’s Enemy: Madness and Myth
in Hamlet, New York: Basic Books. This psychoanalyst’s interpretation is:
“Hamlet kills Polonius more or less in the belief that he is killing Claudius:
‘I took thee for thy better’ (III, iv, 32).”
(5) J. L.
Austin, Pretending (1961). Philosophical
Papers. London: Oxford University Press, pp. 201-219.
(6) Holmes, D.
S. (1990). The evidence for repression: An examination of sixty years of
research. In Singer, J. L. (Ed.) Repression and dissociation: Implications for
personality theory, psychopathology, and health. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press. Pp. 85-102.
(7) Festinger,
L. (1957). A Theory of Cognitive
Dissonance. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
(8) Freud, S.
(1939). Moses and Monotheism. New York: New York: Alfred A. Knopf. In the
book, Freud’s foray into considering Moses an Egyptian, not a Jew, makes note
of the fact that “Moses” was an Egyptian name. But in Exodus Moses was the son of a Hebrew woman who set her infant
adrift in order to avoid his being put to death by the then reigning pharaoh.
He was discovered among the reeds and raised by pharaoh’s daughter, who named
him. Given this, we hardly could have expected him to be called “Melvin.” (Of
course, Finkelstein and Silberman, in their 2001 study of biblical origins,
find no evidence for the migration of a Semitic people out of Egypt across the
Sinai peninsula, casting into doubt events around the Mosaic legend—from start
to finish. Cf. Finkelstein, I. & Silberman, N. A. (2001) The Bible Unearthed: Archeology’s New Vision
of Ancient Isreal and the Origin of its Sacred Texts. New York: Free
Press.)
(9) cf.
Mitchell, S. A. (1993) Hope and Dread In
Psychoanalysis. New York: Basic Books. Mitchell undertakes a intrepid
attempt to reconcile “theories” that are a shambles of splintered sensibility
within contemporary psychoanalytic circles. He purports to show how, like blind
men touching different parts of the elephant, they cling to separate, but
equally warranted formulations. In so doing, he deconstructs the classical
Freudian goal of a “science of behavior,” while maintaining a clubhouse
nostalgia for this tradition. It’s an engineering feat worthy of any
poststructuralist who assures you the “truth” is elusive—except, of course, the
truth that the truth is elusive. Were this not enough, Mitchell’s descriptions
of differences among these groups pulsates with ecumenical fervor: “These are
all good theories. (Others could be added as well.) They are all interesting,
complex, and work within their own terms. It is precisely this rich
heterogeneity of our psychoanalytic world that makes it no longer compelling to
think of psychoanalysis as a method for uncovering a singular truth. Rather,
this rich heterogeneity that has evolved from Freud’s monolithic system makes
it much more compelling to view psychoanalytic theory as a group of
interpretive systems, each with its own principles, laws, and criteria of
verifiability. Object relations theory, self psychology, interpersonal
analysis, Kleinian theory: each of these fully psychoanalytic systems is a
monolith unto itself. But our community of many orthodoxies is a different
world from Freud’s community of one orthodoxy and several splinter movements (such
as Adlerian or Jungian theory).” (Mitchell, 1993, p. 47).
Despite
Mitchell’s encomium for family togetherness, it would be timely to specify
precisely what the “differences” among approaches in his community of True
Believers supposedly amounts to—if this is even possible. To be sure, their
published work abounds in seeming theoretical contrasts. But how do these
relate to actual practices that are
its alleged derivatives? No clear answer to this has been forthcoming—for two
reasons: In vivo transactions between
analysts and analysands are routinely drenched in parochial vocabularies
casting a shroud of mystery over the nature of the data inspiring them. Second, psychoanalytic homage to the privacy
of therapeutic encounters derails searching attempts to investigate connections
between them and the verbiage used to describe them. When Hamlet observed,
“Words, words, words,” he was taking a dim view of the tools we use to convey
external realities.
(10) For a critique of Jacques Lacan’s
lucubrations about mathematics, especially topology, cf. Sokal, A. &
Bricmont, J. (1998). Fashionable
nonsense: Postmodern intellectuals’ abuse of science. New York: Picador
USA.
(11) When new
fossil links are discovered—as they have been in profusion in recent years—the battle
cry on the other side suddenly becomes drawing attention to the missing link
between the newly discovered species and the one immediately preceding it! But
these are minor skirmishes in warring mind-sets that betray what is really at
stake: the fancied threat to religious fundamentalism posed by naturalistic
explanation. When the holiest of one’s beliefs is perceived as embattled,
you’ve got a real fight on your hands convincing the other side that it’s not
possible for Darwinian evolution to threaten something that’s not science to
begin with. Cf. Miller, K. R. (2008) Only
A Theory: Evolution and the Battle for America’s Soul. New York: Penguin
Books.
(12) The
popularity of psychoanalysis in the United States, rivaled only by the
enthusiasm for it in Argentina, was given a booster shot by Hollywood. Aside
from the promotional campaigns for the practice hawked in such films as Spellbound, The Snake Pit, The Lady in
the Dark, The Seven-Per-Cent Solution, David and Lisa, Freud, Tender Is the
Night, An Unmarried Woman, Pressure Point, High Anxiety, and numerous others, tinseltown has for decades
wallowed in chumminess between movie stars and their “analysts.” Writers who
documented the dalliance were prescient about the sordid sociology underlying
the connection: “…the journalist Bruce Bliven visited Los Angeles and told his
readers back east, ‘Here is the world’s prize collection of cranks,
semi-cranks…angry or ecstatic exponents of food fads, sun-bathing, ancient
Greek costumes, diaphragm breathing, and the imminent second coming of
Christ…If psychoanalysis appeared to be little more than another of these
crackpot creeds, that may have had something to do with its less than
auspicious origins in ‘cuckoo land.’” Farber, S. and Green, M. (1993) Hollywood on the couch: A candid look at the
overheated love affair between psychiatrists and moviemakers, New York:
William Morrow and Company, p. 23. On a clinical note, the hope on the part of
many Hollywood stars that their
personality disorders or substance-abuse careers can be spun as
“neurotic” in the technical, albeit currently retired meaning of this term, is
a brazen example of wishful thinking. Assuming such conditions can be
remediated by a treatment approach utilizing dream interpretation or free
association has to be a stunning example of hype marketed for entertainment
kingpins.
(13) Bornstein,
M. (2004) The problem of narcissism in psychoanalytic organizations: The
insularity of power. Psychoanalytic
Inquiry, 24, 71-85. Summers, F. (2008) Theoretical insularity and the
crisis of psychoanalysis. Psychoanalytic
Psychology, 25, 413-424.
(14)
Wittgenstein had this to say about Freud:
“…he is full of
fishy thinking & his charm & the charm of his subject is so great that
you may be easily fooled. He always stresses what great forces in the mind,
what strong prejudices work against the idea of psycho-analysis. But he never
says what enormous charm that idea has for people…There may be strong
prejudices against uncovering something nasty, but sometimes it is infinitely
more attractive than it is repulsive.
Unless you think very clearly,
psycho-analysis is a dangerous & foul practice, & it’s done no end of
harm & comparatively little good…So
hold on to your brains.”
REFERENCES
American Psychiatric Association
(1994). Diagnostic and statistical manual
of mental disorders, fourth edition. Washington, D.C.: American Psychiatric Association.
Austin, J. L. (1960). Sense and Sensibilia. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ayllon, T., and Haughton, E. (1964).
Modification of symptomatic verbal behavior of mental patients. Behavior Research and Therapy, 2, 87-97.
Ayllon, T., and Haughton, E. and
Hughes, H. (1965). Interpretation of symptoms. Fact or fiction? Behavior
Research and Therapy, 3, 1-7.
Balmary, M. (1979). L’Homme Aux Statues: Freud et la Faute
Cachee du Pere. Paris.
Baroja, J. C. (1965). The World of the Witches. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Bowlby,
R. (2004). Introduction to Studies in
Hysteria. London: Penguin Books.
Breuer, J. and Freud, S. (1895). Studies in hysteria. SE, 2.
Carter, K. C. (1983). Infantile
hysteria and infantile sexuality in late nineteenth-century German-language
literature. Medical History, 27, 186-196.
Cioffi, F. (1972). Wolheim on Freud. Inquiry. 15, 171-186.
Cioffi, F. (1974). Was Freud a liar? Listener, 91, 172-174.
Cioffi, F. (1988). “Exegital
myth-making” in Grünbaum’s indictment of Popper and exoneration of Freud. In P.
Clark and C. Wright (Eds.), Mind,
Psychoanalysis, and Science. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 61-87.
Cohen, L., Berzoff, J. and Elin M.
(1995). Dissociative Identity Disorder. Northdale,
New Jersey: Jason Aronson, Inc.
Crews, F. (1986). Skeptical Engagements. New York: Oxford University Press.
Crews, F. (1995). The Memory Wars: Freud’s Legacy in Dispute. New York: New York
Review of Books.
Crews, F. (Ed.) (1998). Unauthorized Freud: Doubters Confront a
Legend. New York: Viking.
Ebersole, P. and Ebersole, S.
(1993). The Abuse of Innocence: The McMartin Preschool Trial. Buffalo, New York: Prometheus Press.
Ellenberger, H.F. (1970). The
Discovery of the Unconscious. New York Basic Books.
Erdelyi, M. (1984). The recovery of
unconscious (inaccessible) memories: Laboratory studies of hypermnesia. In G.
Bower (Ed.), The Psychology of Learning
and Motivation: Advances in Research and Theory, Vol. 18, New York:
Academic Press, pp. 95-127.
Erwin, E. (1993). Philosophers on
Freudianism. In J. Earman, et. Al., Philosophical problems of the internal and
external worlds. Essays on the
philosophy of Adolph Grünbaum. Pittsburgh
and Konstanz: University of Pittsburgh Press and Univestätsverlag, pp. 409-460.
Esterson, A. (1993). Seductive Mirage: An Exploration of the Work
of Sigmund Freud. Chicago,
Illinois: Open Court.
Farrell, J. (1996). Freud’s paranoid quest: Psychoanalysis and
modern suspicion. New York: New York University Press.
Féré, C. S. (1884). La famille névropathique: Theorie
teratologique de l’hérédité et la dégénerescence, Archives de Neurologic, 7, 1-43.
Fish, S. (1986). Withholding the
missing portion. Power, meaning and persuasion in Freud’s “The Wolf Man” Times Literary Supplement. August 29,
935-938.
Fishberg, M. (1911). The
Jews: A Study of Race and Environment. New York: W. Scott.
Freud, S. The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund
Freud. 24 volumes. James Strachey
(Ed.) London: Hogarth Press and the Institute of Psycho-Analysis (1953-1974).
(Hereafter referred to as SE).
Freud, S. (1988). Hysteria. SE, 1, 41-57.
Freud, S. (1896a). Heredity and the
aetiology of the neuroses. SE, 3,
143-146.
Freud, S. (1896b). Further remarks on
the neuro-psychoses of defence. SE, 3,
162-185.
Freud, S. (1896c). The aetiology of hystera. SE, 3, 191-221.
Freud, S. (1905). Three essays on the
theory of sexuality. SE, 7, 123-243.
Freud, S. (1912-1913). Totem and taboo. SE, 13, 1-161.
Freud, S. (1918). From the history of
an infantile neurosis. SE, 17, 7-123.
Freud, S. (1925). An autobiographical
study. SE, 20, 7-74.
Freud, S. (1931). Female sexuality. SE, 21, 221-243.
Freud, S. (1964). The Letters of Sigmund Freud. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Freud, S. (1886a). Report on Freud’s
studies in Paris and Berlin. SE, 1.
Freud, S. (1886b). Preface to the translation of Charcot’s
lectures on the diseases of the nervous system. SE, 1.
Freud, S. (1893). Charcot, SE, 3.
Gay, P. (1988). Freud: A Life For Our Time. New York: Doubleday.
Gilman, S. (1993a). Freud, Race, and Gender. Princeton, New
Jersey: Princeton University.
Gilman, S. (1993b). The Case of Sigmund Freud: Medicine and
Identity at the Fin de Siecle. Baltimore, Maryland: The John Hopkins
University Press.
Glicklhorn, J. and Glicklhorn, R.
(1960). Sigmund Freuds academische
Laufbahn im Lichte der Dokumente. Vienna and Innsbruck: Urban &
Schwartzenberg.
Gould, S. J. (1981). The Mismeasure of Man. New York: W. W.
Norton.
Grünbaum, A. (1979). Is Freudian
psychoanalytic theory pseudo-scientific by Karl Popper’s criterion of
demarcation? American Philosophical Quarterly, 16, 131-141.
Grünbaum, A. (1984). The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A
Philosophical Critique. Berkeley, California: University of
California Press.
Grunbaum, A. (1991). Etiology and
therapy in psychoanalytic theory. Behavioral
and Brain Sciences, 14, No. 4., December, 729-732.
Hacking, I. (1995). Rewriting the Soul: Multiple Personality and
the Sciences of Memory. Princeton,
New Jersey: Princeton University Press.
Henningsen, G. (1969). The papers of
Alonso de Salazar Frías: A Spanish witchcraft polemic 1610-14. Temenos. Studies in comparative religion
presented by scholars in Denmark, Finland, Norway, and Sweden, 5, 85-106.
Henningsen, G. (1980). The Witches’ Advocate: Basque Witchcraft and
the Spanish Inquisition. Reno, Nevada: University of Nevada Press.
Israels, H. and Schatzman, M.
(1993). The seduction theory. History of Psychiatry. 4, 23-59.
Kern, S. (1973). Freud and the
discovery of child sexuality. History of
Childhood Quarterly, 1, 117-141.
Krasner, L. (1958). A technique for
investigating the relationship between the behavior cues of the examiner and
the verbal behavior of the patient. Journal of Consulting Psychology, 22, 364-366.
Krull, M. (1986). Freud and His Father. New York: Norton.
Levin, K. (1944). Freud’s Early Psychology of the Neuroses: A Historical Perspective,
Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Lynn, S. and Rhue, J. W. (1994). Dissociation. New York: Guilford Press.
Macmillan M. (1991). Freud Evaluated: The Completed Arc, New
York: North-Holland.
Masson, J. M. (1984). The Assault on Truth: Freud’s Suppression of
the Seduction Theory, New York: Farrar, Straus, and Girox.
Masson, J. M. (1985). The Complete Letters of Sigmund Freud to
Wilhelm Fliess: 1887-1904, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University
Press.
McGrath, W. J. (1986). Freud’s Discovery of Psychoanalysis: The
Politics of Hysteria. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press.
Monter, E. W. (1969). European Witchcraft, New York: John
Wiley.
Murray, C. and Herrnstein, R. J.
(1994). The Bell Curve. New York: The
Free Press.
Sachs, D. (1989). In fairness to Freud:
A critical notice of The foundations of
psychoanalysis by Adolph Grünbaum. The
Philosophical Review, vol. XCVIII, No. 3, July, 349-378.
Salzinger, K. and Pisoni, S.
(1958). Reinforcement of affect
responses of schizophrenics during the clinical interview. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 57, 84-90.
Schatzman, M. (1992). Freud: Who
seduced whom? New Scientist, 21, March, 35-37.
Schimek, J. G. (1987). Fact and fantasy
in the seduction theory: A historical review. Journal of the American Psychoanalytical Association, 35, 937-965.
Sebald, H. (1995). Witch-Children: From Salem Witch-Hunts to Modern Courtrooms. Amherst,
New York: Prometheus Books.
Smith, M. and Pazder, L. (1980). Michelle Remembers. New York: Congdon
and Lattes.
Stewart, L. (1976). Freud before
Oedipus: Race and heredity in the origins of psychoanalysis. Journal of the History of Biology, 9, 215-228.
Stratford, L. (1988). Satan’s Underground. Eugene, Oregon:
Harvest House.
Sulloway, F. (1991). Reassessing
Freud’s case histories: The social construction of psychoanalysis Isis 82, 245-275.
Sulloway, F. (1992). Freud: Biologist of the Mind. Cambridge,
Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
Szasz, T. S. (1961). The Myth of Mental Illness: Foundations of a
Theory of Personal Conduct, New York: Harper & Row.
Thornton, E. M. (1983). The Freudian Fallacy: An Alternative View of
Freudian Theory. Garden City, New Jersey.
Vetter, I. (1988). Die Kontroverse um Sigmund Freuds sogennante Verfuhrungtheorie. MA
thesis Bayern: Catholic University Eichstatt.
Weber, E. (1986). France, Fin de Siècle. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Belknap Press of
Harvard University Press.
Webster, R.
(1996). Why Freud Was Wrong: Sin, Science
and Psychoanalysis. New York:
Harper Collins.
Wilcocks, R. (1994). Maelzel’s Chess Player: Sigmund Freud and
the Rhetoric of Deceit. Lanham,
Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield.
Young-Bruehl, E. (1995). A history of
Freud biographies. In Micale, M. S. and
Porter R. (Eds.), Discovering the History
of Psychiatry, (pp. 157-173). New York: Oxford University Press.
No comments:
Post a Comment