Published as an Op Ed piece in the Litchfield
County Times, December 12, 2008
Abortion, Church Law, and the Endless Controversy
David Begelman
How
far back does the raging controversy over abortion go? Certainly not to biblical
times. There is no revealed or scriptural underpinning for the antiabortion
position in the Old or New Testaments, as St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas
both noted. Abortion must have been practiced during biblical eras, yet there
is no scriptural indication the practice commanded moral attention, much less
prohibition. Does the omission weaken an ancient grounding for pro-life
ideology?
For a major period of church history,
theologians accepted Aristotle’s embryology. The Greek philosopher held there
were three stages in the development of human actuality. His doctrine of
progressive animation provided that the soul was not present at the creation of
a new human body. St. Augustine harbored continuing doubts about the timing of
ensoulment. He averred we should not profess to know that about which we are
ignorant. Gratian, the Bolognese monk and author of the Decretum, a definitive codification of canon law, declared no one
could be considered a “murderer” who aborts a fetus before the soul is in the
body. Papal endorsement of progressive animation was a dominant theological
theme up to the sixteenth century. During that era, Pope Gregory XIII held it
was not murder to destroy an embryo before ensoulment, because “it was not
human.”
St. Thomas mirrored the opinion of many
centuries of doctrine on the matter when he held that it was murder to abort a
fetus with a soul and sinful, although not murder, to abort one without a soul
since this meant the destruction of potential human life. For him, that this
second act was not actually murder did not render it morally permissible.
All
this, of course, was to change. Gregory’s successor, Sixtus V, in his bull Effaenatum of 1588, ruled that all
abortions were murders. His opinion was rendered null and void by his
successor, Pope Gregory XIV. In 1621, the theologian Paulo Zacchia attacked the
doctrine of progressive animation, although the more influential theologian,
St. Alfonsus Ligouri, came to its defense in the eighteenth century. The
uncompromising view of Sixtus was revived in 1869 by Pope Pius IX. One year
later, Vatican I enunciated the doctrine of papal infallibility.
Since Sixtus V in the sixteenth
century held that all abortion was murder, it is a mistake to assume that it
was the discovery of the sperm, ovum, and fertilization process that accounts
for why theologians pushed the onset of life back to conception. Fertilization
as a biological process was an 1875 discovery, and the ovum was discovered by
von Baer in 1827. However, Sixtus’s bull predates such discoveries by three
centuries.
Pro-life and pro-choice ideologues
tend to frame the controversy over abortion in misleading terms. The issue does
not, as they would have it, center around when “human life” begins, but when personhood or the soul is created. Human life is
a biological concept, the basic unit of which is the cell. Of course human life
is destroyed during abortion; but so is it destroyed during premature
ejaculation, menstruation, manicures, appendectomies, and haircuts. The
unfertilized egg or spermatozoa are likewise “human life” because, unlike
celery stalks or monkey germplasm, they are human cellular units.
Personhood
is a legal/philosophical concept, one at the center of an issue over an entity
that has rights, property, or identity, whereas soul is a theological concept. The three concepts are logically
distinguishable, and do not map easily onto one another—precisely the reason
why the abortion controversy is such a complex one.
If
one of the bases for the pro-life position is an assumption about ensoulment, then scientific information
concerning human ontogenesis would appear to be irrelevant to strengthening the
position. There is no “scientific,” secular, or medical foundation for the
existence or non-existence of souls.
Accordingly, the ploy of displaying the formation of the embryo in utero is
utterly beside the point in promoting pro-life ideology when the concept soul is at the center of a debate. We should
refrain from broaching the problem of abortion by mixing up concepts gleaned from
independent strands of discourse.
On
the other hand, the pro-life assumption of the creation of personhood at
conception, irrespective of its religious origins, cannot be countered by
pro-choice arguments involving a woman’s so-called “right to choose.” No person
has an imagined right to choose to murder another person, on the theory the
fertilized egg is a person. The pro-choice objection to this, that those who
believe in the creation of the soul or
personhood at conception should not impose their religious views on others who
do not share it, will not do. It does not matter how pro-lifers come to
appropriate the view that the fertilized egg is a person; they feel obliged to
defend the rights of the fetus so conceptualized, and that no extraneous
argument about a mother’s “right to choose” has relevancy when the life or
death of a person is at stake.
The
wrinkle in the pro-life position is the contradiction many of its proponents
seem to incur when they brook such exceptions to the impermissibility of abortion,
as in cases of rape or incest. If a mother’s “right to choose” is regarded as irrelevant
in preserving the sanctity of life, why should the way in which a woman is
impregnated form exceptions to the inviolability of the same principle? The
unwanted pregnancy by forcible means would seem to have no bearing on the preservation
principle if the embryo is a person. Is it any less deserving of protection
than the embryo created in a loving way? The pro-lifer who speaks of such
exceptions to the principle of preserving life (many social conservatives do)
is either contradicting his or her ideology, or else tacitly believes fertilized
eggs may not be “human beings” in certain cases.
What
about cases in which fertilized ova are expelled by natural processes, like
miscarriages? Pro-lifers do not regard such accidents as deserving the special care
appropriate for a deceased family member. There are no rituals like religious
prayers at burial sites, church events, or baptisms on “persons” expelled as
miscarriages. Material thus expelled is usually unceremoniously flushed away.
Does the attitude implied in such perfunctory action indicate that pro-lifers
do not regard miscarriages as involving the death of individuals, a
contradiction in the pro-life ideological stance if persons or souls are created
at conception?
Danbury
News-Times, 8/31/12, Letters to the Editor, James S. Mellett:
“By
counting the number of actual pregnancies that follow implantations, we can get
an idea of the actual loss of fertilized eggs and embryos.
Based
on research done on thousands of women, the embryo loss is about 70 percent,
and that does not count the loss between fertilization and implantation, which
runs at least 50 percent according to in vitro studies on humans.
If
we extrapolate the miscarriage results backward, we can estimate that 90
percent of all fertilized eggs never make it to term…One can only conclude as
did former Dominican priest and eminent geneticist Francisco Ayala, that God is
the greatest abortionist of all.”
No comments:
Post a Comment