Tuesday, April 22, 2014


Albert Camus and His World: Here Comes the Sun!


David Begelman


Albert Camus and his contemporary Jean-Paul Sartre, have reputations that pretty much survive in broad conceptual brushstrokes. This, although their interactions were often in the nature of continued squabbling and on occasion, peevishness. Maybe their increased distancing from each other fueled Camus’ unwillingness to be classified as an existentialist, perhaps not. But the rupture in their relationship in all likelihood removed him further from the ideas of the philosopher who authored the turgid L'Être et le Néant (Being and Nothingness). As Camus famously remarked:

“No, I am not an existentialist. Sartre and I are always surprised to see our names linked. We have even thought of publishing a short statement to which the undersigned declare that they have nothing in common with each other and refuse to be held responsible for the debts they might respectively incur…when we did get to know each other, it was to realize how much we differed. Sartre is an existentialist, and the only book of ideas that I have published, The Myth of Sisyphus, was directed against the so-called existentialist philosophers” (Camus, 1968, p. 345).

Camus’ reluctance to be called an existentialist lacks clarity absenting elucidation of just what “existentialism” is to begin with. We await a precise answer from commentators conversant with the movement. Far from articulating its meaning precisely, they have yet to come up with something that has definitional transparency.

The doctrine is sometimes spun as “Existence precedes essence,” (l’existence précède l’essence) a Sartrean sound bite taxing understanding inasmuch as it’s difficult to comprehend how ontological status can be ascribed to a featureless something before its “essences” color the existential palette. Persons come bundled in this or that attribute before existentialists of whatever stripe take to refashioning them.  If the expression is shorthand for stressing the idea that persons are free to decide their destinies before any classifactory system prefigures this, it may amount to a persuasive definition (Stevenson, 1938) of humankind, not one that necessarily jibes with the way we are constituted. Moreover, boundaries of self-determination are often constrained by the contingencies of time, place, and capacity. A starving African child has far less latitude to make life-defining choices than a French Nobelist.

Sartre himself said his existentialism “means that…man exists, turns up, appears on the scene, and only afterwards defines himself. If man, in the existentialist scheme, is indefinable it is only because he is nothing, Only afterwards will he be something, and “he will have made what he will be” (Roemer, 1995). Needless to say, this patter is not much help in clearing away the conceptual cobwebs. I should like to think that we are somethings, however pristine, from the get-go; not nothings about which something might later be said!

As far as the history of existentialism is concerned, its spokespersons have a tendency to reify concepts like “being” or verbs like “exists” in ways that are troublesome. Sometimes it seems as though they’re putting forth ideas that can be likened, Heidegger-like, to the proposition that because nobody beats Kasparov at chess, one grandmaster, Nobody, is capable of the feat (Carnap, 1932,1978; Ayer, 1947).   

A familiar wisdom has it that existentialism is the thing Nietzsche, Kierkegaard, Heidegger, Berdyaev, Marcel, Merleau-Ponty, Jaspers, de Beauvoir, Tillich, Barth, Shestov, Bultmann, Sartre and Camus all share. Talk about mixed crowds squeezed into a Procrustean bed of commonality! Not to mention the conspicuous omission of Protagoras, especially when it comes to his notion of ἄνθρωπος μέτρον (“Man is the measure of all things”). What more suitable banner might be waved should an anthropic view of the world be an overriding existentialist mantra? In addition, we have the Third Century C. E. church father and failed Montanist, Tertullian, who, in his De Carne Christi voiced the sentiment, “Credo quia absurdum” or “Prorus credible est, qua ineptum est,” roughly translated as “I believe it because it is absurd,” doubtlessly a note of joyful wonder to numerous “existentialists.” H. L Mencken was later to quip that, “Needless to say, he began life as a lawyer” (Mencken, 1946).

 

*  *  *

 

Camus’ love affair with his homeland, Algeria, never ended. He came from a family of pied-noirs, or colloquially dubbed “black feet,” originally French settlers of North Africa who, according to folklore, traipsed into their homes with muddied footware.

One senses that Camus’ life was a trajectory born of conflicting sentiments. His upbringing was one of deprivation and a less than nurturing home life in his grandmother’s cramped apartment in the Belcourt section of Algiers, close to the Arab quarter. From this impoverished background he segued into more intellectual and literary pursuits at the University of Algiers, a far cry from the earthier existence that was his original lot. Formerly, he had worked at selling car parts, as a private tutor, a salesman, police clerk and worker at a meteorological institute. And all this dotted with bouts of tuberculosis that demanded respite from days on the soccer field. The rest is history, although his take on his earlier life was not without a nostalgic look backwards.

Like his hero Sisyphus (Camus 1975), Camus insisted that he was happy with his life despite its earlier adversity. Even the harsh treatment by his grandmother (she used a whip to discipline), the early death of his father in World War I in 1914, his mother’s physical and emotional handicaps, bouts of pulmonary distress, not to mention panic attacks and depressions, did little to quell his enthusiasm for days by the Mediterranean seaside and the warmth of its sun. The flavor of his romance with the Algerian landscape is noticeable in his many essays, as well as one passage from his Love of Life:

“There lay all my love of life: a silent passion for what would perhaps escape me, a bitterness beneath a flame. Each day I would leave this cloister like a man lifted from himself, inscribed for a brief moment in the continuance of the world…It was at these moments that I truly understood what countries like this could offer me. I am surprised men can find certainties and rules for life on the shores of the Mediterranean, that they can satisfy their reason there and justify optimism and social responsibility. For what struck me then was not a world made to man’s measure, but one that closed in upon him. If the language of these countries harmonized with what echoed deeply within me, it was not because it answered my questions but because it made them superfluous. Instead of prayers of thanksgiving rising to my lips, it was this Nada whose birth is possible only at the sight of landscapes crushed by the sun” (Camus, 1968, p. 56). Is it any wonder the posthumous collection of his essays is entitled “Lyrical and Critical Essays”?

There were, of course, other facets of the story. Camus’ encomium for life under the Algerian sun includes a quite different strand of sentiment. Take, for example, the passage in Nuptials:

“At the neighborhood movie houses in Algiers, they sometimes sell pastilles with engraved red mottoes that express everything needed for the birth of love: (A) questions: “When will you marry me?”; “Do you love me?”; (B) replies: “Madly”: “Next spring.” After having prepared the ground, you pass them to the girl next to you, who answers in kind or simply plays dumb. At Belcourt, there have been marriages arranged like this, whole lives decided in an exchange of mint candies. And this gives a good picture of the childlike people of this country” (Camus, 1968, p. 86).

“Childlike,” indeed—except, possibly, for those of the country who authored treatises on Plotinus and St. Augustine and went on to win Nobel Prizes! Evidently, as in most parts of the world, Algerians come in all shapes and sizes. In the manner of “existentialists” who defy being stuffed into one philosophical niche, they are not all of them attracted by “sensual delights” or “amusements” that Camus designated elsewhere in Summer in Algeria are “idiotic” (Camus, 1968, p. 87).

One receives the strong impression that much of Camusean discourse was tied up in a flirtation with and tension among matters of the mind, spirit and body. And when it came to beguiling rhapsodies about his homeland in North Africa, one senses it was difficult for him on occasion to suppress traces of condescension—for all the delights his country had to offer. The failing is apparent in other passages in which Camus takes back with one hand what he gives with the other. Thus:

“Yet here is a race without past, without tradition, and yet not without poetry—but a poetry whose quality I know well, harsh, carnal, far from tenderness, that of their very sky, the only one in truth to move me and bring me inner peace. The contrary of a civilized nation is a creative nation. I have the mad hope that, without knowing it perhaps, these barbarians lounging on beaches are actually modelling the image of a culture in which the greatness of man will at last find its true likeness. This race wholly cast into its present lives without myths, without solace. It has put all its possessions on this earth and therefore remains without defence against death” (Camus, 1975, p. 135).

Both Sartre and Camus, despite their real or imagined differences, were on the cusp of a French post-war media craze as leading European intellectuals. Rumor has it that another strand in their estrangement was Sartre’s discomfort with Camus’ popularity, good looks and attractiveness to women. Philandering on wives of quite different dispositions, Simone Hié, a morphine addict, and Francine Faure, a mathematician, was not a rare pastime for the writer, given as he was to dalliances with many women, including Patricia Blake, Catherine Sellars and Maria Casarès. The last named lover broke with him in 1945 after discovering his wife Francine was pregnant. The role was not a new one for the actress. She starred as “Nathalie,” the spurned lover of the mime Baptiste (Jean-Louis Barrault) in Marcel Carné’s memorable 1945 film Les Enfants du Paradis). Might the homely Sartre’s lamentation: “L’enfer, c’est les autres” (“Hell is other people” in his drama Hui Clos) be a sour grapes theme driven by a strictly personal agenda? But this is speculative, and detracts from very real differences between the two writers. One of these involved political issues, in contrast to their philosophical—and not always transparent—musings.

Camus abandoned communism before Sartre, although both writers were previously staunch defenders of the ideology. Sartre was intolerant of Camus’ more modulated solution to the unrest between Algerian rebels and French colonial interests, while Camus rejected Sartre’s support for revolutionary violence likewise championed by leading left-wingers of Europe. Yet a Camus-like political stance in another racial divide was to find expression in Nelson Mandela’s African National Congress, a movement that sought to reconcile the conflict between white Afrikaners and a secessionist black constituency. Others have drawn the same comparison (Djebar, 2000).

A flavor of Camus’ heroic stance in the face of the intransigence of warring political factions is suggested by many passages in Algerian Chronicles (Camus, 2013), including:

“On the left, we hear justice repeatedly cited as a excuse for affronts to any authentic idea of justice. The Right has thus ceded the moral response entirely to the Left, while the Left has ceded the patriotic response entirely to the Right. France has suffered from both reactions, The country needed moralists less joyfully resigned to their country’s misfortune and patriots less willing to allow torturers to act in France’s name. Metropolitan France has apparently been unable to come up with any political solution other than to say to the French of Algeria, “Die, you have it coming to you” or “Kill them all, they’ve asked for it.” Which makes for two different policies but one single surrender, because the real question is not how to die separately but how to live together” (2013, pp. 28-29).

 Camus despised totalitarianism and the oppression of the poor and disenfranchised, and felt that any political resolution of the French/Arab clash had to avoid bloodshed at all costs. Despite the ups and downs of Camus’ political views throughout his life, his antipathy to capital punishment was finalized while writing for the newspaper Combat, and became his conviction to the end.

For a thinker who emphasized the “absurdity” of existence, Camus’ political track record on his resistance to the Nazi regime and efforts to contribute to a resolution of the Algerian crisis would appear to clash dramatically with the tenets of any such philosophical position. Yet Camus to the end insisted that resistance to tyranny was not incompatible with his emphasis on the meaninglessness of life. He continued to emphasize his metaphysical position on absurdity, even in the context of believing in the possibility of human resolutions, political or otherwise. Some such counterpoint between the shifting nature of his ideas about absurdity and the efficacy of human action is suggested in The Rebel (L’Homme révolté), where he concludes that one interpretation of absurdity is contradictory. While it lays claim to believing in nothing, it nonetheless believes in its own capacity to protest or resist, as well as what such resistance can accomplish. Again, considering Camus’ outspoken efforts and campaigns for the downtrodden and persecuted, regarding him as a “philosopher of the absurdity of life” seems oddly out of whack with this courageous strand in his thinking.

 

*  *  *

 

The internet has this to say about the relevant concept: In philosophy, "the Absurd" refers to the conflict between (a) the human tendency to seek inherent value and meaning in life and (b) the human inability to find any. In this context absurd does not mean "logically impossible", but rather "humanly impossible’" The universe and the human mind do not each separately cause the Absurd, but rather, the Absurd arises by the contradictory nature of the two existing simultaneously. Absurdism, therefore, is a philosophical school of thought stating that the efforts of humanity to find inherent meaning will ultimately fail (and hence are absurd) because the sheer amount of information as well as the vast realm of the unknown make certainty impossible. And yet, some absurdists state that one should embrace the absurd condition of humankind while conversely continuing to explore and search for meaning. As a philosophy, absurdism thus also explores the fundamental nature of the Absurd and how individuals, once becoming conscious of the Absurd, should respond to it.”

One can, of course, contend that any conceivable response to the “absurd” character of human existence might incorporate the very trait it was supposedly recruited to explore. Aside from this, there are several terms that coelsce in “existentialism” and Camus’ discourse. Among these are “absurdity” and “meaninglessness,” not always synonomous in ordinary parlance.

Some philosophers define “absurd” more narrowly to cover situations in which there is “a conspicuous discrepancy between pretension or aspiration and reality” (Nagel, 1970, p. 718). The discrepancy, however, is only be a necessary, not  sufficient, condition of absurdity under Nagel’s definition. There are countless instances in which aspirations fail to achieve goals without any hint of “absurdity,” in the philosophically relevant or ordinary senses of the term. Moreover, it is questionable whether such formulae do justice to a term that roves more indiscriminately over the semantic landscape. Because of this, it ostensibly confounds attempts to make it undergird such grandiose enterprises as a doctrine of Absurdism.

As commonly observed, the term “absurd” describes an idea, a person’s behavior, or an object or situation arousing amusement or derision. A situation, argument, or remark thus can be “absurd.” When life or existence in general is taken to illustrate the concept, as presumably instantiated in “your pants falling down as you are knighted” (one of Nagel’s examples), one wonders whether “absurdity” in the existentialist lexicon tends to become a case of galloping extrapolation. If the absurdity of a knighted person’s trousers falling down is illustrative of something about life at large, why doesn’t well-buckled and securely fastened trousers—as are most pairs of the item in knighting rituals throughout history—illustrate the very opposite, that however checkered life is with angst, aburdity or futility, it is also bursting with sensible meaning and coherence? Extrapolation can go both ways. Yet Nagel feels the pervasive absurdity of existence is a plausible idea, while Solomon (2006) avers that an omnipresent sense of absurdity “poisons our everydayness and gives our every  experience a tinge of futility” (p. 37). Nagel goes on:

“The sense that life as a whole is absurd arises when we perceive, perhaps dimly, an inflated pretension or aspiration which is inseparable from the continuation of human life and which makes it absurdly inescapable, short of escape fom life itself” (Nagel, 1970, p. 718). Yet he is also mindful of differences between the individual case or situation and overarching philosophical formulations:

“Many people’s lives are absurd, temporarily or permanantly, for conventional reasons having to do with their particular ambitions, circumstances, and personal relations. If there is a philosophical sense of absurdity, however, it must arise from the perception of something universal—some respect in which pretension and reality clash for us all. This condition is supplied, I shall argue, by the collision between the seriousness with which we take our lives and the perpetual possibility of regarding everything about which we are serious as arbitrary, or open to doubt” (Nagel, 1970, p. 718).

It should be noted that there are two senses of the “universality” of the clash between pretension and reality: (1) we all have experienced the disparity in the ongoing challenges of daily life, because what most of us sometimes want or strive for is frustrated—in some cases, most of the time, versus (2) everything all of us want or strive for is arbitrary and open to doubt, and is therefore encumbered by a sense of absurdity. I take it that the Absurdist thesis is that individuals who cannot bring themselves to adopt outlook (2) and opt for (1) have not taken the true pulse of life.

All the same, a philosopher who elects to promulgate “Absurdism” has to confront the fact that there still may be varying degrees of absurdity that go unmentioned and unexplored in his formulation. In this respect, just what does the doubt, meaninglessness, and contingent aspect of life amount to for any individual in any situation? When I boil an egg on the stove, it is not suddenly transformed into a chandelier on one occasion and a cucumber on yet another. So there are a great many regularities in my existence I depend on anchoring me in the reality receiving a bad press in Absurdism. Yet were I confronted with unexpectedly appearing chandeliers or cucumbers, might you suppose Absurdists would fasten on this to reiterate their same point of view about life? But surely there is a momentous difference between a world in which an egg remains an egg and one in which I am jolted by its turning suddenly into chandeliers and cucumbers!

Furthermore, fine-tuning “absurdity” is paradoxically absent in Absurdist discourse. In a world of unpredictably debuting objects, are their appearances staggered? That is, can I inevitably count on a cucumber appearing  after a chandelier, or is the sequence randomized? And isn’t the randomization of experience more absurd—however the term is defined—than its alternative of regularized, because staggered, presentations? Despite the possibility of shades of absurdity, not a word in Camusian or Sartrean discourse about how their central concept can come packaged in augmented or attenuated forms! The semantic variability of absurd is also a characteristic of expressions like meaning, meaningful and meaningless (or meaninglessness). Nozick (1981) has reviewed eight senses of “meaning” that infiltrate ordinary discourse.

Going on, it is far from obvious that a world depleted of meaning has to be one that is absurd in the sense of “illogical” or “irrational.” There are clinical conditions—those frequently accompanied by suicidal thoughts, plans or intentions, in which the world seems emptied of meaning and pleasure (ahedonia) although not perceived as “absurd,” at least not in the ordinary sense of the term. Persons who are in major depressions describe their experiential world just this way, although it is not the one inhabited by Camus characters like Jean-Baptiste Clamence in The Fall (La Chute). This narrator was a lawyer so invested in making speeches about himself and his experiences, it is safe to say that in the Freudian sense he is cathected to the external world in spades. The same is true for Patrice Meursault in The Stranger (L’Êtranger) or Dr. Bernard Rieux in The Plague (La Peste).

Whatever strains of ruefulness infiltrate the psychologies of sundry Camus characters, the hard edge of the clinical condition is seldom, if ever, in sight. Those characters don’t report the sting of anything akin to major depression, despite all the talk about the absurdity of life. Possible exceptions are unnamed persons in The Myth of Sisyphus referred to by Camus who seem to have a psychiatric condition. In that treatise, Camus cites cases in which “…many people die because they judge that life is not worth living,” and contrasts these with cases in which some “paradoxically” get “killed for ideas or illusions that give them a reason for living.” The contrast here suggests the one between instances of psychiatric and political or issue-oriented significance. The former type seems to be represented by cases in which Camus declares a person experiences “…the absence of any profound reason for living, the insane character of that deadly agitation and the uselessness of suffering” (1975, p. 13).     

On the other hand, most literary existential heroes have a mind-set that would capture the interest of philosophers, not necessarily psychiatrists. But it is nonetheless one that Camus takes to be how his characters define the self and the world. So we are off and running, without, it may be said, any intention to psychiatricize those literary characters.

An intriguing character in Camus’ The Plague is Father Paneloux, for he is the one who has a familiar take on the figure lurking persistently behind the scenes in these discussions, God. Paneloux is a Jesuit priest whose view of the plague devastating the Algerian city of Oran is, naturally, unlike the Camus-like atheism of other characters in the novel. He believes that God is loving and, as in the mind-set of American evangelists like Jerry Falwell and Pat Robertson, believes the plague is both a test of faith as well as a scourge sent by the deity for the punishment of earthly sins. Whatever the scope of Paneloux’s prattle about divine punishment and a supervising God, he delivers sermons predicated on religious understandings of blight flourishing since the infancy of our species. As such, they reflect a system of belief that purports to supply answers to riddles about life that existentialists, believers or otherwise, likewise address.

Paneloux is intriguing as a character because the “absurdity” of the world is a pan-existentialist theme that both Sartre and Camus celebrate as driven by, inter alia, the absence of religious absolutes in a system of understanding. Paneloux’s trust in the Almighty places him squarely in the other tradition, although his reliance on faith to the exclusion of being treated by physicians for his terminal ailment suggests he may harbor traces of Mary Baker Eddy’s Christian Science, in contrast to St Ignatius Loyola’s Catholicism.

All the same, it is questionable whether God, Paneloux-style or otherwise, can rescue anyone from existential angst, since religious thinkers as committed as Kierkegaard—reputedly the philosopher who kicked off the existentialist movement—were not spared the outlook likewise adopted by atheists like Camus and Sartre. Does this mean that with or without God, we are still fated to be saddled with their anguished view of life? And if this, why all the fuss? After all, Camus and Sartre were both fully engaged in a world of political struggle even granting their morose view of life. Accordingly, the Absurdist frame of mind would appear to be redundant when a hero, literary or otherwise, takes a stand against the depredations of history. 

The lesson here is that if atheism isn’t the lynchpin for the view that life is absurd or meaningless, why pretend that it is? And if God is incapable of supplying meaning, or relieving meaninglessness or absurdity (because he failed to do so in the cases of Kierkegaard and Gabriel Marcel), we are led, as the poet says, to an overwhelming question: what would?

The objection to this might be that human life just happens to be the kind of thing freighted with absurdity, the truth or falsity of religion notwithstanding. If there is no way out of the dilemma of life’s meaninglessness, the challenge then becomes specifying the possible (i.e., hypothetical) structure of an experienced world that would alleviate the problem, make matters different than they are. If no answer is forthcoming, what are we talking about? Is existentialist discourse itself conceptually threadbare, given a definition of “meaninglessness” all too familiar to philosophers: that which characterizes an empty proposition, statement, belief, philosophy. If there is no conceivable alternative to the absurdity or meaninglessness of the world, is the claim that it is, alas, vacuous?

Let’s go on. I start to see a patient who complains of suicidal thoughts and feelings of emptiness. Life offers “no hope” for him, and he reports a pervasive experience of the “meaninglessness” of everything. There are also collateral neurovegetative symptoms, like appetite and sleep loss, loss of libido and anhedonia. He is not an existentialist, nor should we draw any connection between his symptoms and this philosophy. That is not the point. What is?

Let’s say the patient, for want of a better expression, has a blin about the world. It’s not as tolerable as the one depicted in philosophies like Camus’ or Sartre’s. What he experiences is a quite intense, pervasive thing—far worse, it may be conjectured, than Antoine Roquentin’s “disgust for existence” in Sartre’s Nausea (Sartre, 1964). This fictional character has a blin about the world also, but notches down from the one perceived by our patient in a major depression. He is “not at all inclined to call myself insane; I see clearly that I am not” (p. 2). In fact, Roquentin experiences disgust with the world in a sort of sweetish form (une  espèce d’écoeurement douceâtre) of detachment or alienation, very short of a state of mind that would benefit from a regimen of SSRIs (selective serotonin reuptake inhibitors).

One way of putting the matter is to say our patient has a condition, not a philosophy or world view (although it is conceivable he or she might develop one based upon an exceedingly morbid view of everything). We are convinced what he or she needs is psychological care and/or medication, not philosophical enlightenment. But the contrast here does not mitigate the fact that both the patient and Roquentin (as well as all of Camus’ heroes from Caligula to Sisyphus) have blins about the world that differ in scope, intensity, and the likelihood of suicide. So what are the weighty differences among them all that speak to something important?

We are tempted to say that the patient’s perception of the world needs to be treated and restored to normalcy; that is, to an outlook that is salutary, not one mired in a depressive state. We want to help him or her achieve a more ordinary, sane blex, not the blin that is the result of malfunctioning neurotransmitters. We want to assist the patient out of his condition so that he sees the world as blex-like. What this amounts to may for the moment be indeterminate; its outlines may be blurred, yet to be specified or sharpened in detail. But we feel we have a general idea of what we mean. (Actually, there are an untold number of perceptions of the world we would deem antidotes to the patient’s blin, if put to the challenge of delineating them.) So while we have refrained from describing at length the blex that should be a desired perception of things, we know for sure it couldn’t be like the blin that is the patient’s world—which is why we consider him to have a “condition.”

Another consideration: the yardstick of a blex is not that it has to be suffused with a happy or optimistic coloration; only that in some requisite way it is an appropriate mind-set, shorn of a blin-like overlay like that of our patient that masks it,. And far from the primacy of any feel-good measure of a blex, it is possible to harbor a blin that involves an overly “happy” perception of the world. Such blins are called manias. No literary existential hero has one, unlike countless persons who experience bipolar disorder or a toxic “high.” The point is that in adumbrating the outlines of a blex, we should avoid ratcheting up the euthymic or hyperthymic quotient to a point of diminishing returns.

A word of warning. We have defined blex as a desideratum. If this is taken to mean “things as they truly are,” we may have bargained for more than we surmise. In this, we distinguish between blin and blex as though the latter were the real world, whereas the former were a sort of artificial, subjective overlay that distorts “reality.” Is this a legitimate move?

What if it turned out that blex is nothing other than a blin meeting with conventional approval and sanction? It’s not as though our depressed patient is insulated from a reality that can be metaphysically authenticated, established or endorsed; only that he is in a condition we feel moved to help change out of a moral concern for his suffering. We’d adopt the same remedial stance even if his dismal blin were the real blex, on the assumption that our conventional notion of blex turned out to be nothing other than a parochial blin we happened to mistakenly identify with external reality! This opens the door to questioning the metaphysical status of any contender for a blex including, naturally, those put forth in the writings of writers like Camus or Sartre.

Unless I am mistaken, both philosophers suppose that the “absurdity” and “meaninglessness” of life is a blex, not merely a blin they have  manufactured or artificially grafted onto things. In other words, they seem to be insinuating that others who do not see the world as they do experience different blins about it that do not match the proper blex-like texture of reality. But should the very notion of the latter fall under an epistemic cloud for both existentialists and those of drastically differing persuasions who have their own notions of blex, we are left with a surfeit of contender blins that proliferate without, it may be said, any way to charter a meaningful course to a bedrock blex the authenticity of which can be conceptually established sub specie aeternitatis. We’ll come back to this conundrum.

Returning to our depressed patient, there are currently some therapeutic approaches to his condition that not only have an efficacious track-record, but in addition do not include biomedical modalities like medication. They are grouped under the rubric cognitive-behavioral therapies (CBT), and often include assisting a patient to alter the cognitions, beliefs, or self-statements the practitioner believes contribute to (or create) his mental problem (Beck, 1967, 1972, 1975; Ellis, 1977, 1994). The thinking among CBT practitioners is that an incorporated belief-system associated with the affective (i.e., emotional) character of the depressed state is the culprit responsible for the latter, as it is with a variety of maladaptive patterns. Accordingly, to modify constituent beliefs about the self and the world is a pathway to eradicating the entire symptomatic picture. In many research studies, although not all, this has more or less proved to be the case. In other words, it is an incorporated belief system about the world or the self that is the target of therapeutic efforts in majorly depressed patients. The therapeutic approach is called cognitive restructuring. But precisely what misconceptions about the self or the world is the putative therapeutic target? Here’s where it gets tricky.

CBT practitioners, if pressed to make a concession to the spirit of “existentialist” philosophy, might grant that there is something “absurd” about the patient’s world. But the psychotherapist only means by this that the patient harbors “absurd,” “irrational” beliefs or cognitions about himself (not the facticity of the world around him) that are at the bottom of his psychiatric problem. In other words, the patient’s problem consists basically in his irrational interpretation of certain events that give rise to his depressed state. He believes it is the thought process of the patient that is illogical, not life, the world or existence itself.  Let’s see what this might mean.

The patient experiences an event. He develops a belief or theory about it which is a misconception; he then experiences an emotional response quite in accord with said misconception, resulting in his “condition,” a depression that requires treatment.

Take an example. The patient is a lawyer who is a very different kind of person than the attorney of Camus’ The Fall, Jean-Baptiste Clamence. He has argued a case unsuccessfully in court, whereupon the defendant he represented is sent to prison for a long term. The lawyer misinterprets this event to prove his personal inadequacy as a litigator, which misconception is at the root of his subsequent despondency requiring treatment. Again, we are not here referencing a case similar to the plight of any character in a Camus novel.

The CBT practitioner addresses the clinical problem by attempting to counteract the patient’s belief that he is personally inadequate based upon his failure to win the court case. He might, for example, attempt to convince the patient that he’s got to appropriate a more realistic mind-set of “You win a few, lose a few,” or reference the spotty track-record of famous litigators, or rely on other arguments to show that the patient is drawing a false, irrational or “absurd” conclusion about himself from the paltry reason that he didn’t win one court case. He might urge the patient to remember how many difficult cases he did win prior to the one failure he misconstrues as proof of professional incompetence.

In an important sense, the success of the CBT approach consists in incorporating a technique of exhortation or argumentation. The relevant metaphor here is that psychiatric status is much like a jury, responding to an attorney’s (psychotherapist’s) appeal to examine critically the case for the assumptive guilt of a defendant. And if the jury is won over, the depression will be alleviated because its cognitive foundation, that the lawyer is inadequate or a failure, will have been undermined. What does all this have to do with Camus?

The CBT practitioner—and I trust I am not mischaracterizing him or her—raises no questions about whether the lawyer’s depression can conceivably be or not be a blex—as opposed to merely a maladaptive blin, essentially because the therapist is not interested in metaphysical conjecture. In the course of his or her professional activities, procedures are not predicated upon assumptions about the true nature of reality, as though therapeutic techniques were driven by covert philosophical positions. He knows the patient’s blin makes him dysfunctional, end of story. And efforts to rid him of it are designed to alter his psychiatric state for a more satisfactory mode of adjustment, purely and simply.

Now suppose the CBT therapist after successfully treating his patient were to take a course in existentialism at a local university campus. After completing it with a passable grade, he thinks back to his therapeutic success with the lawyer, and begins to pose questions quite in accord with what he has learned in his recent coursework. “I helped my patient to achieve a more satisfactory adjustment to be sure, but now I have other types of questions about the treatment.” One he poses is: “Am I entitled to say that I helped my patient to see reality better, become in touch with the blex, not the artificial and maladaptive blin that is the result of his depressive state of mind?” (And here we are speaking about blex as the emotional texture of the world, not simply the character of a belief, illogical or otherwise.) 

The therapist here engages in some chancy speculation, if only because approaching the issue this way can conceivably raise searching questions about why his patient’s depression has to be construed as merely a dysfunctional blin, and not a blex that, however maladaptive or disagreeable, is the true nature of “reality.” Maybe we are all of us bamboozled by the temptation to regard the world as something that is at bottom vastly different from the way it seems to majorly depressed patients. It is but a stone’s throw from this mind-set to drawing parallels to the discourse of Camus and Sartre. Maybe, as they declare, the blex is “absurd,” “illogical” “meaningless,” or some such existential concept! (It is questionable whether the disparity between Sartre’s view that the world itself is absurd and Camus’ view that it is only the relation between the person and his world comes to a weighty difference.)

We can move ahead, it seems to me, in two distinguishable ways: (1) take up the challenge of determining philosophically the true nature of blex, on the assumption that Camus and Sartre might, for all we know, be correct in their view about the absurdity of life, or (2) contend that deliberations or theories about the true nature of blex are at bottom nonsensical since there is no way to even hypothetically adjudicate contrasting metaphysical claims.

As a footnote, we assume that the Camus/Sartre view that existence or the world is “absurd” isn’t captured by the notion that life is frequently  unfair, inconvenient or unpredictable. We hardly need Camus or Sartre to assure of us something we all of us know as a daily reminder of what it is to be alive, and before the two developed their respective philosophies. Moreover, is it the empirical features of experience that inspire existentialist philosophies, or the subjective outlook on the world favored by them? If the former, is existential angst or “absurdity” at bottom only a selective focus on a world of seeming that includes as many uplifting and “meaningful” experiences as well as their presumed antitheses? Is not the world just as often fair, convenient and predictable? Again, and in line with (2), how is the true nature of blex conceivably established should the focus be on the externality of meaning, in contrast to conflicting mind-sets we bring to experience?

Sartre himself was prescient about the stakes in all of this. In the very first pages of Nausea he reflects, “So a change has taken place during these last few weeks. But where? It is an abstract change without object. Am I the one who has changed? If not, then it is this room, this city and this nature: I must choose” (Sartre, 1964, p. 4). Maybe he must; but his choice doesn’t guarantee it will be the right one—should talk about rightness here make any sense at all. Tolstoy registered remarkably similar sentiments when he revealed, “But five years ago something very strange happened to me. At first I experienced moments of perplexity and arrest of life, as though I did not know what to do or how to live…They were always expressed by the questions; what is it for? What does it lead to?” (Tolstoy, 1940, pp. 14-15).  

A reminder: in none of this, does an issue revolve around the empirical features of the world. The existential heroes of Camus and Sartre apprehend the factual world in precisely the same way as anyone when it comes to sensory perception. The sun of Camus’ Mediterranean beach is the same sun for everyone, but may cause a variety of reactions, just as it does when bathers sustain differently tanned skins while under it: “When you frequent the beach in summer you become aware of a simultaneous progression of all skins from white to golden to tanned, ending up in a tobacco-colour which marks the extreme limit of the effort of transformation of which the body is capable (Camus, 1975, p. 129). More often than not, and as most dermatologists are wont to remind us, you’d be doing yourself a favor staying out of a blazing sun, on the beach or elsewhere!

 

                                               *  *  *

 

Camus’ The Myth of Sisyphus addresses several issues, two of which are notable, although the first, ideas about suicide, has been given the lion’s share of attention. He declares that “Judging whether life is or is not worth living amounts to answering the fundamental question of philosophy” (Camus, 1975, p. 11). The second issue is contained in the terminal paragraph of the treatise:

“I leave Sisyphus at the foot of the mountain! One always finds one’s burden again.But Sisyphus teaches the higher fidelity that negates the gods and raises rocks. He, too, concludes that all is well” (Camus, 1975, p. 111).

It strikes me that the second of these themes, Sisyphus’s happiness in futility, is the more intriguing one. As for the first, it remains a mystery why suicide should be a philosophical problem for Camus, much less a fundamental one, in exploring the possibility of a relationship between it and absurdity. As we know, Camus finally opted for life—albeit in the form of resistance in the face of absurdity—thus uncoupling the sapience of suicide from his doctrine of Absurdism. Yet there is a certain tension, if not contradiction, in Camus’ discussion of the “exact degree to which suicide is a solution to the absurd” since “The principle can be established that for a man who does not cheat what he believes to be true must determine his action. Belief in the absurdity of existence must then dictate his conduct” (Camus, 1975, p. 14). However, by framing the issue this way, Camus implies that an argument, however covert or verbalized, can be mounted for or against suicide, given the meaninglessness of life. But the final decision, whatever it turns out to be, is delivered under the auspices of a supervisory rationalism vetting the proper connection between central concepts! (Jeanson, 1947). To argue the necessity of resistance to absurdity is already to concede the game to the philosophic or rationalistic mind-set Camus has taken enormous pains to repudiate. After all, Camus reminded us in 1942 that absurdity teaches us nothing (Camus, 2008, p. 24). 

Moreover, there is something oddly out of keeping with an existentialist or Absurdist who raises a question about a compelling aspect of suicide, when at the heart of his philosophy is the primacy of one’s free decision. Regarding absurdity as any kind of reason to consider suicide might, from a Sartrean point of view, illustrate bad faith (mauvaise foi). It would be akin to pleading a case for or against it, as though any such deliberation diminished or augmented what comes down to a freely undertaken, unimpeded decision!

To recapitulate the plight of Sisyphus, Camus writes:

The gods had condemned Sisyphus to ceaselessly rolling a rock to the top of a mountain, whence the stone would fall back of its own weight. They had thought with some reason that there is no more dreadful punishment than futile and hopeless labor” (1975, p. 107).

In Greek mythology, Sisyphus was no innocent victim of divine punition. In the Iliad, Homer describes him as “wily,” a manipulator. On other versions of the myth, he was a murderer, seducer, betrayer and trickster extraordinaire. In one, he chained Thanatos, incurring the displeasure of Ares, who became irate that no warrior could die in battle with Death thus shackled. Sisyphus, whatever the magnitude of his effront to the gods, illustrates only too well what a lopsided contest it is when mortals have the temerity to incur their wrath. In this, he is well within the tradition of other mythological heroes whose fates must be reckoned stunning cases of overkill. (Shakespeare was later to extend the same heavy hand to Malvolio of Twelfth Night and Shylock of The Merchant of Venice, should anyone harbor the view that the Bard always had his sympathetic characters arrange to make the punishment fit the crime.)

Sisyphus is often grouped in a triumvirate along with the equally hapless Ixion and Tantalus, both consigned to forms of eternal punishment. These were contrived as just desserts by a heavenly host with nothing better to do than arrange extravagant forms of comeuppance. Ixion, after killing his father-in-law and lusting after Hera, was bound by Hermes to an eternally spinning fiery wheel. Tantalus, in one version of his myth, is said to have pilfered ambrosia and nectar from Zeus’s table on Mount Olympus. For this infraction he was made to stand for all eternity in a pool of water under a fruit tree. When he reached for the fruit, its branches would recede; when he bent down to drink the water, the latter would do the same thing.

Lessons about the catastrophic upshot of crossing the gods is evident everywhere in Bulfinch (2010). And that fabulous wayfarer, Odysseus (considered in some mythological accounts to be a son of Sisyphus), illustrated what it meant should one arouse the ire of a deity—in his case, Poseidon.

Unlike Ixion and Tantalus, who seem immobilized in their torture, one wonders why Sisyphus didn’t simply walk away from his repetitive task. After all, his slippery personality was clearly in evidence in other chapters of his career. The king of Corinth (formerly Ephyra), Sisyphus was a stockpile of surprises during his lifetime, having turned the tables previously on quite a number of characters: Zeus, Thanatos, Hades, Autolycus (who made the fateful mistake of stealing his cows), Salmoneus, Asopus, Persephone and Merope. Even if the gods were to contrive another punishment for disobeying the ground rules of his ultimate rock-and-roll caper in Tartarus, could it be any worse than the task Taylor (1991) for one considers to be the epitome of futility? And given our hero’s aptitude for trickery, why not arrange yet another wily scheme to elude his sentence?

 The other strand to the story that Camus underscored bears repeating:

“One does not discover the absurd without being tempted to write a manual of happiness…Happiness and the absurd are two sons of the same earth. They are inseparable.” And again: “All Sisyphus’ silent joy is contained therein. His fate belongs to him. His rock is his thing” and “There is no sun without shadow, and it is essential to know the night” (Camus, 1975, p. 110)

Camus concludes his treatise with the memorable peroration:

“But Sisyphus teaches the higher fidelity that negates the gods and raises rocks. He, too, concludes that all is well. This universe henceforth without a master seems to him neither sterile or futile. Each atom of that stone, each mineral flake of that night-filled mountain, in itself forms a world. The struggle itself towards the heights is enough to fill a man’s heart. One must imagine Sisyphus happy.” (Camus, 1975, p. 111).

There are enough remarks about futility/meaninglessness being paired with happiness/joy in The Myth of Sisyphus to leave us puzzled over the juxtaposition. Just why are these polarities joined together by Camus? The challenge here would be the task of uncovering some point to Camus’ unusual pairing.

Camus, it may be observed, was hardly one to disparage the possibility of happiness in an otherwise absurd world. When he did, it was only in connection with what he construed as the pie-in-the-sky fantasies of religion. In Nuptials he declared that “there is no superhuman happiness…I can see no point in the happiness of angels” (Camus, 1968, p. 90)—manifestly because he felt as an atheist no such emotions existed. But he harbored them in his own life, as when he delighted in basking under the sun of an Algerian beach.

The Camus essays of the 1930s document the writer’s conviction that living life to the hilt—and this means savoring all the worldly, sensual joys one might experience—is possible once the yoke of the transcendental is repudiated. But this only dramatizes that a Camusian world is one that sets its face against theism and the promise of everlasting life. In the so-called existentialist literature of other philosophers within the fold, “absurdity” seems to take on significance only as it contrasts with a prevailing religious view of the world. “Meaninglessness” for many of them seems to be forever waiting in the wings before the Nietzschean dictum of “God is dead” becomes an order of the day.

There are numerous thinkers who maintain that there is a close relationship between belief in a deity and the meaningfulness of life. Craig (1994) for one asserts emphatically that “For if there is no God, then man’s life becomes absurd” (p. 40). This writer goes on to declare that immortality alone without God is empty from the standpoint of meaning: “But it is important to see that it is not just immortality that man needs if life is to be meaningful. Mere duration of existence does not make that existence meaningful. If man and the universe could exist forever, but if there were no God, their existence would still have no ultimate significance” (p. 42). 

The “meaningfulness of life” in Craig’s scheme of things must pertain to an externally derived awareness of absurdity. For there are many atheists like Hitchens (2007), Dawkins (2006), Harris (2004), Dennett (2006) and Krauss (2012) whose view of the world absenting a godhead encompasses one richly endowed with meaning. Craig’s conception of them must be a group whose existence is meaningless, although they don’t know this! According to him, these atheists, unlike Sartre and Camus, don’t perceive the absurdity of life that their atheism presumably encourages at every turn.

Perhaps Camus would never have considered suicide in a world in which God, heaven and a system of steadfast religious absolutes prevail. Yet even under a perspective of eternality, perhaps he should have. After all, might not suicide be broached, given a life hitched to transcendental meaning—a.k.a. unremitting, because guaranteed, monotony? Should such a conclusion seem implausible, is Camus’ conjecture that life will be experienced better only when it is viewed as meaningless any the less counterintuitive? (Camus, 1975, p. 53). Nozick (1981) for one took up the challenge of critically examining the notion that the idea of “meaning” is ineluctably linked to religious belief.

Those contemporary writers who, far from extolling the virtues of a presiding godhead, consider religion to be a case of dictatorship by a deity whose principal function is to monitor every thought and deed on pain of eternal punishment. For them, it is the epitome of totalitarian rule, much like a celestial North Korea (Hitchens, 2007). On a lighter note, a similar opinion was registered in the third act of G. B. Shaw’s Man and Superman, in which characters from Mozart’s Don Giovanni convene to discuss the merits of heaven compared to the alternative establishment:

“Ana: But why doesn’t everybody go to Heaven, then?

The Statue: (chuckling) I can tell you that, my dear. It’s because heaven is the most angelically dull place in all creation: that’s why.

The Devil: His excellency the Commander puts it with military bluntness; but the strain of living in heaven is intolerable. There is a notion that I was turned out of it; but as a matter of fact nothing could have induced me to stay there. I simply left it and organized this place.

The Statue: I don’t wonder at it. Nobody could stand an eternity of heaven.

The Devil. Oh, it suits some people. Let us be just, Commander: it is a question of temperament: I don’t understand it; I don’t know that I particularly want to understand it; but it takes all sorts to make a universe. There is no accounting for tastes: there are people who like it. I think Don Juan would like it” (Shaw, 1960, pp. 362-363).

Meaningfulness-cum-religion is a package deal combining the idea of God with salvation and the immortality customarily yoked to it. Yet Nozick for one has questioned why the idea of “meaningfulness” gets forever coupled with timeless being:

“It is often assumed that there is a problem about the meaning of life because of our mortality. Why does the fact that all people die create a special problem? (If life were to go on forever, would there then be no problem about its meaning?)” (Nozick, 1981, p. 579). Mark Twain observed that while eternality sounds comforting in the pulpit, when you try it on for size you’ll see how heavy time will hang on your hands.

Considered differently, it may be redundant to ask why Camus assigns any particular emotion to Sisyphus, consigned as the latter is in myth to the futile task of rolling a rock endlessly up a hill. After all, Camus’ version of Sisyphus is only a fictional construction, differing from the protagonist of the ancient story. Camus reminds us that “Nothing is told us about Sisyphus in the underworld” and that “Myths are made for the imagination to breathe life into them” (Camus, 1975, p. 108). However, having been punished by the gods, Sisyphus suffers a plight we would assume is other than “happiness.” Why should Camus consider Sisyphus to be saddled with an emotion seemingly out of keeping with a plight devised as comeuppance as dispensed by the gods? As Taylor (1991) suggested—almost as a way out of the counterintuitive corner he feels Camus is in—Sisyphus’s “happiness” might be a possibility had he constructed a temple with his rocks atop the hill he rolled them up, however long this took. That would be at least one foundation for positing a less than resigned and hopeless hero. In the absence of any such felicitous denouement, what can we make of the Camusian case for happiness? How is it possible to envision it in an individual consigned to an enduringly futile plight in any case? Were we committed to explicating how “happiness” could conceivably characterize the mind-set of the toiler beset with his endless task, we might seek to determine whether there are matching instances in real life serving to justify this possibility.

In the all too familiar notion of capture-bonding, hostages or prisoners subjected to brutal or even sadistic treatment by their captors may get to harbor positive—even affectionate—feelings toward them, on occasion defending them when they come under criticism or judicial review. The FBI has amassed a data-base of individuals who “confuse” the occasional absence of abuse on the part of their captors with solicitude or kindness. According to the agency, fully 8% of a population of victims so treated illustrate what has come to be known as the “Stockholm syndrome.” The name of the pattern is derived from a robbery in Sweden in which bank employees held as hostage in a hold-up in a vault developed emotional attachments to their captors. This was expressed in rejecting assistance from the police force during a six day ordeal, and defending the robbers even after the hostages were freed. Some commentators (Henson, 2006) feel similar psychological processes may be operating in military basic training, the battered wife syndrome and fraternity hazing, not to mention a variety of other kinds of punitive situations.

It is not the author’s present purpose to argue that Sisyphus illustrates a Stockholm syndrome, purely and simply. The syndrome pertains to the attitude of victimized persons toward their persecutors. Sisyphus’s mind-set in the Camusean spin on him is about his predicament, not other persons—although its sympathetic tone parallels the one of victims in the capture-bonding paradigm. Yet the two vastly different cases may nonetheless represent instances of a common principle or process. For example, in documented cases of capture-bonding, the victim’s experienced world may become a sort of closed system within which such things as “harshness,” “brutality,” “kindness” or “generosity” become distinctions that take on newer meanings. Thus, a captor who is less cruel or arbitrary on Tuesday than he was on Monday is no longer perceived as either of these, but as kind or generous in virtue of the relatively more positive disposition. It’s as if distinctions ordinarily drawn in normal, outside situations were reversed or transposed in the newer system. The effect for all individuals in similar situations is not ordained, and most traumatic experiences at the hands of captors are recounted negatively. Accordingly, there is no way to predict which victim will undergo capture-bonding after being subjected to whatever harsh treatment is his or her unfortunate lot. Where does this leave Sisyphus?

For Camus, Sisyphus is not alone in his take on a burden he is forced to bear. He is matched by Sophocles’ Oedipus and Dostoyevsky’s Kirilov, both of whom conclude that “All is well” despite their terrific burdens  (Camus, 1975, p.109). “The descent is thus sometimes performed in sorrow, it can also take place in joy. The word is not too much” (Camus, 1975 p. 109). Does Camus mean that the task in question is always one of joy, or encased in a system of fluid meanings in which joy and sorrow alternate with each other? The latter possibility sounds like the process underlying the capture-bonding paradigm, in which familiar, albeit contrasting, emotions are reversed or transposed. A rock is thus not configured as a burdensome thing to roll up a hill simpliciter. It is perceived as either more or less burdensome than the one rolled up the day before. The onerous task then gets unpacked as one in which comparisons among “bad,” “better,” “worse” and “best” achievements flourish.

Could this be what Camus means by happiness and the absurd being “two sons of the same earth”? It’s a guess, and maybe a poor one. Be that as it may, considering it as a possibility should prompt us to acknowledge that in the best and worst of all possible worlds, one thing is a surety: the necessity of drawing distinctions. Whether life is absurd may be up for grabs in some philosophical quarters; but making distinctions about experiences is pretty much a done deal as the world turns—and I mean any world. 

 

REFERENCES

 

Ayer, A. J. (1947) The Claims of Philosophy. Polemic, 7, pp. 18-33.
 
Beck, A.T. (1967) The Diagnosis and Management of Depression. University of Pennsylvania Press.

Beck, A.T., (1972) Depression: Causes and Treatment. University of Pennsylvania Press.

Beck, A.T., (1975) Cognitive Therapy and the Emotional Disorders. International Universities Press.

Bulfinch, T. (2010) Bulfinch’s Mythology. Charleston, South Carolina: CreateSpace Independent Publishing Platform.

Camus, A. (1975) The Myth of Sisyphus. London: Penguin Books.

Camus, A. (1968) Lyrical and critical essays. New York: Vintage Books.

Camus, A (2008) Notebooks: 1952-1959. Chicago: Ivan Dee.

Camus, A. (2013) Algerian Chronicles. London, England: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

Carnap, R. (1932) The Elimination of Metaphysics Through Logical Analysis of Language, trans. Arthur Pap, in A. J. Ayer (ed.), Logical Positivism, New York: The Free Press, 60–81.

Carnap, R. (1978) The overcoming of metaphysics through logical analysis of language, in Michael Murray (Ed.)  Heidegger and  modern philosophy, New Haven: Yale University Press, p. 26.


Craig, W. L. (2000). The Absurdity of Life Without God. In E. D. Klemke (ed.), The Meaning of Life, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 40-56.


Dawkins, R. (2006). The God Delusion. New York: Houghton Mifflin.


Dennett, D. (2006) Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon. New York: Penguin Books.

Djebar, A. (2000) Algerian White: A Narrative. New York: Seven Stories Press.

Ellis, A. (1977) Handbook of Rational-Emotive Therapy, with Russell Greiger & contributors. NY: Springer Publishing.

Ellis, A. (1994) Reason and Emotion in Psychotherapy, Revised and Updated. Secaucus, NJ: Carol Publishing Group, 1994.

Harris, S. (2004). The End of Faith: Religion, Terror, and the Future of Reason. New York: W. W. Norton.

Henson, K. (2006). Evolutionary Psychology, Memes and the Origin of War, Mankind Quarterly, 46.

Hitchens, C. (2007) God is Not Great: How Religion Poisons Everything. New York: Twelve Books.

Jeanson, F. (1947). Albert Camus ou le mensonge de l’absurdité, Revue Dominicaine, 53.


Krauss, L. (2012). A Universe From Nothing: Why There is Something Rather than Nothing. New York: Free Press.


Mencken, H. L. (1946). Treatise On the Gods. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.

Nagel, T. (1970). ‘The Absurd’, Journal of Philosophy, 68, 716-27; reprinted in Life and Meaning: A Reader, (ed.) O. Hanfling, 49-59, Oxford: Blackwell, 1987.

Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

Roemer, Michael (1995). Telling Stories: Postmodernism and the Invalidation of Traditional Narrative. Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield, p. 221.


Sartre, J. P. (1964). Nausea. New York: New Directions Publishing.

Shaw, G. B. (1960)  Plays by George Bernard Shaw. New York: Signet Classics.


Solomon, R. Dark Feelings, Grim Thoughts. New York: Oxford University Press.


Stevenson, C.L. (1938). "Persuasive Definitions." Mind,  47,  331–350.

Taylor, R. (1991). Metaphysics (4th Edition). Pearson: Upper Saddle River, New Jersey.


Tolstoy, L. (1940). A Confession. World Classics Edition. London: Oxford University Press.  

 

No comments:

Post a Comment